Formal fuzzy logic

From Citizendium
Revision as of 09:46, 23 October 2008 by imported>Giangiacomo Gerla (→‎Effectiveness)
Jump to navigation Jump to search
This article is developing and not approved.
Main Article
Discussion
Related Articles  [?]
Bibliography  [?]
External Links  [?]
Citable Version  [?]
 
This editable Main Article is under development and subject to a disclaimer.

To be Completed !! Template:TOC-right

Introduction

Formal fuzzy logic, or "fuzzy logic in narrow sense", is a relatively new chapter of formal logic. Its aim is to represent predicates which are vague in nature as big, near, or similar (for example), and to formalize the reasonings involving these predicates. The notion of a fuzzy subset, proposed by L. A. Zadeh since 1965, plays a crucial role, since a vague predicate is interpreted by a fuzzy subset. In the sequel, we will write "fuzzy logic" instead of "formal fuzzy logic", but notice that in literature the name "fuzzy logic" comprises a large series of topics based on the notion of a fuzzy subset and which are usually devoted to applications.

We can consider fuzzy logic as an evolution and an enlargement of multi-valued logic since all the definitions and results in the literature on multi-valued logic are also considered in fuzzy logic. There are two basic approaches to fuzzy logic. The first one, proposed by P. Hajek and by a large series of students, is strictly closed to the tradition of multi-valued logic. Indeed the logical consequence operator works on a given classical subset of hypotheses to give the related classical set of logical consequences. Equivalently, the entailment relation is a crisp one. This is obtained, as it is usual in multi-valued logic, once a set of designed truth values is fixed. We call, ungraded approach, in brief U-approach, such a way to face fuzzy logic. Another approach was proposed by J. A. Goguen, J. Pavelka and many authors and it is rather out of line with the tradition of multi-valued logic. Indeed, the logical consequence operator works on a given fuzzy subset of hypotheses (the available information) to give the related fuzzy subset of logical consequences. Equivalently, the entailment relation is a fuzzy relation. We call graded approach, in brief G-approach such a way to face fuzzy logic.

As in multi-valued logic, the starting point is a valuation structure, i.e. a bounded lattice L equipped with suitable operations to interpret the logical connectives. The minimum 0 means 'False', the maximum 1 means 'True', the remaining elements intermediate truth values. The following is the main class of valuation structures (see Hájek 1998, Novák et al. 1999 and Gottwald 2005).


Definition A standard algebra is an algebraic structure ([0,1], , , 0,1) where is a continuous triangular norm i.e. a continuous, associative, commutative, order preserving operation such that 1 = 1 and is the related residuation, i.e. = sup{z | y}.


The main examples of standard algebras are obtained by assuming that is the minimum (Zadeh logic), the usual product (product logic) or that x y = Max{x+y-1,0} (Lukasievicz logic). In addition, several authors consider also languages with logical constants to denote rational truth values. Once a valuation structure is fixed, the semantics of the corresponding propositional calculus is defined in a truth-functional way as usual. In first order fuzzy logic the semantics is defined as follows.


Definition. A fuzzy interpretation of a first order language is a pair (D,I) such that D is a nonempty set and I a map associating (as in the classical case) every n-ary operation name h with an n-ary operation in D and every constant c with an element I(c) in D. Moreover, I associates every n-ary predicate name r with an n-ary L-relation I(r) : Dn L in D.


Then, the only difference with classical logic is that the interpretation of an n-ary predicate symbol is an n-ary L-relation in D. This enables us to represent properties which are "vague" in nature. Given a fuzzy interpretation we can evaluate the formulas as follows where, given a term t, we denote by the corresponding function we define as in classical logic.


Definition. Let (D,I) be a fuzzy interpretation, then for every formula α whose free variables are in and in D, we define the truth degree Val by induction as follows

Val
Val = ValVal
Val = ValVal
Val = Inf d є D Val.

In the case there is a propositional constant c* corresponding to a truth value c, we set

Val = c.

Observe that in the case L is not complete it is possible that a quantified formula cannot be evaluated. We call safe an interpretation such that all the formulas are evaluated. As usual, if α is a closed formula, then its valuation does not depend on the elements and we write Val instead of Val. More in general, given any formula α, we denote by Val the valuation of the universal closure of α.

The ungraded approach

In the ungraded approach one considers a subset Des of [0,1] whose elements are called designed truth degrees. The interpretation is that in Des there are the truth degrees which one considers sufficient to claim the validity of a formula. Usually one sets Des = {1}.


Definition. Let (L, , , 0, 1) be a fixed standard algebra. Then we say that a fuzzy interpretation (D,I) is a model of a formula α provided that Val(I,α) is a designed value. Let T be a theory, then (D,I) is a model of T if every formula in T is satisfied in (D,I). We write T α if every model of T is a model of α. The related logical consequence operator is defined by setting

D(T) = {α : T α}


The deduction apparatus in the ungraded approach is defined by adopting the same paradigm of classical logic, i.e. a deduction relation is defined by a suitable set of logical axioms and suitable inference rules. A fuzzy logic is axiomatizable provided that a deduction apparatus exists such that coincides with . Unfortunately, the main fuzzy logics are not axiomatizable.


Theorem. In almost all the fuzzy logics the logical consequence operator is not compact. This entails that these logic are not axiomatizable.


As an attempt to bypass such an obstacle, in the ungraded approach one proposes a different entailment relation related with the variety generated by a given triangular norm.


Definition. Given a standard algebra ([0,1], , →,0,1), denote by Varl() the class of all linearly ordered algebras in the variety generated by ([0,1], , →, 0, 1). Then a Varl()-interpretation is an interpretation in a valuation algebra belonging to Varl(). Given a set T of formulas and a formula α, we write T Varl() α provided that every safe Varl()-model of T is a safe Varl)-model of α. The related logical consequence operator is defined by setting

DVarl()(T) = {α : TVarl() α}.


The logics related with the entailment relation Varl() works well. In fact, the following theorem holds true.


Theorem. In almost all the fuzzy logics the entailment relation Varl() is compact and therefore these logics are axiomatizable provided that we refer to such an entailment relation.


A criticism for such a solution is that in Varl() there are unnatural valuation structures. As an examples structures with infinitesimal truth values. This is rather far from the uman intuition. Moreover, while the completeness of [0,1] entails that all the quantified formulas are valuated, in the case we refer to the variety Varl(), we have to admit unsafe interpretations.

The graded approach: approximate reasonings

The graded approach is perhaps closer to the spirit of fuzzy logic. In fact the aim of any logic is to elaborate (uncomplete) information and, in the case of fuzzy logic, should be natural to admit an information like "the truth values of α is between λ and μ", i.e. a constraint on the possible truth value of a formula. Taking in account that for a large class of fuzzy semantics we can split such an interval constraint into the two lower bound constraints "the truth values of α is greater or equal to λ" and "the truth value of α is greater or equal to 1-μ", the following definitions are proposed.


Definition . Consider a fuzzy theory s, i.e. a fuzzy subset of formulas. Then a fuzzy interpretation (D,I) is a model of s, in brief (D,I) s if Val(I,α) ≥ s(α). The logical consequence operator is the map Lc : [0,1]F → [0,1]F defined by setting

Lc(s)(α) = Inf{Val(I,α) : (D,I) s}.


Equivalently we can define a graded entailment relation by setting s λ α provided that λ = Inf{Val(I,α) : (D,I) s}. Such a definition is in accordance with the fact that the information carried on by s is that, for every sentence α, the value s(α) is a "constraint" on the unknown truth value of α. More precisely s(α) is a lower bound for such a value. Again, the value Lc(s)(α) is a "constraint" on the unknown truth value of α. As a matter of fact it is the better constraint we can find given the information s.

In the graded approach we can obtain a deduction apparatus by extending the Hilbert's approach as follows.


Definition. A fuzzy inference rule is a pair r = (syn,sem) where syn, the syntactical part, is a partial n-ary operation in F (i.e. an inference rule in the usual sense) and sem, the semantical part, is an n-ary joing-preserving operation in [0,1]. An evaluated syntax is a structure (la,R) where la is a fuzzy set of formulas we call fuzzy subset of logical axioms, and R is a set of fuzzy inference rules.


The meaning of an inference rule r is:

- IF we are able to prove at degree , respectively
- AND we can apply syn to
- THEN we can prove at degree .

Usually, n00 = 2 and sem1,...,λn) is a product like λ1 λ2. As an example, the fuzzy Modus Ponens is defined by assuming that the domain of syn is the set {(α, α→β): α,β are in F}, by setting syn(α, α→β) = β and by assuming that sem(λ,μ) = λμ. This rule says that if we are able to prove α and α → β at degree λ and μ, respectively, then we can prove β at degree λμ.


Definition. A proof π of a formula α is a sequence of formulas such that = α, together with a sequence of related justifications. This means that, for every formula , we have to specify whether

i) is assumed as a logical axiom or;

ii) is assumed as an hypothesis or;

iii) is obtained by a rule (in this case we have to indicate also the rule and the formulas from used to obtain ).


The justifications are necessary to valuate the proofs. Indeed, let s be the fuzzy subset of proper axioms and, for every i ≤ m denote by π(i) the proof . Then the information furnished by π given s is the value Val(π,s) is defined by induction on m by setting

Val if is assumed as a logical axiom
Val if is assumed as an hypothesis
Val if there is a fuzzy rule such that with i(1) < m,...,i(n) < m.

Now, unlike the usual deduction systems, in a fuzzy deduction system different proofs of a same formula α may give different contributions to the degree of validity of α. This suggests the following definition.


Definition. The deduction operator is the operator D defined by setting

D(s)(α)= Sup{Val(π,s)| π is a proof of α}.

A fuzzy logic is axiomatizable if there is a fuzzy deduction system such that Lc = D.


Notice that under some natural hypotheses, a fuzzy propositional logic is axiomatizable if and only if the logical connectives are interpreted by continuous functions (see Gerla 2001). As was shown in Novak 2007, the following axiomatizability theorem holds true.


Proposition. Lukasiewicz firs order logic is axiomatizable.


Effectiveness

In the ungraded approach to fuzzy logic a test to analize the effectiveness is to consider the set of all tautologies. Now, since two possible entailment relations are defined, we have to consider two corresponding notions of tautology.


Definition Given a standard algebra (L, , , 0, 1) a formula α is a standard tautology if it is satisfied in every fuzzy interpretation in (L, , , 0, 1). The formula α is a general tautology if it is satisfied in every safe Varl()-interpretation.


In the U-approach the following negative result holds true.


Theorem In the case of Lukasiewicz and product logic the set of standard tautologies is not recursively enumerable (see B. Scarpellini (1962)).


Such a fact gives a further confirm on the impossibility of an axiomatization of the entailment relation Failed to parse (unknown function "\proves"): {\displaystyle \proves} , and it leads to focalize the attention on Failed to parse (SVG (MathML can be enabled via browser plugin): Invalid response ("Math extension cannot connect to Restbase.") from server "https://wikimedia.org/api/rest_v1/":): {\displaystyle \proves} Varl(). At this regard, one proves the following theorem.


Theorem. For each continuous t-norm , the set of general -tautologies in first order logic is Σ1-complete (and therefore recursively enumerable).


In the case of the graded approach to face the question of the effectiveness we have to give a suitable notion of effectiveness for fuzzy sets. A first proposal in such a direction was made by E.S. Santos by the notions of fuzzy Turing machine, Markov normal fuzzy algorithm and fuzzy program. Successively, in L. Biacino and Gerla 2006 the following definition was proposed where Ü denotes the set of rational numbers in [0,1].


Definition A fuzzy subset s : S [0,1] of a set S is recursively enumerable if a recursive map h : S×N Ü exists such that, for every x in S, the function h(x,n) is increasing with respect to n and s(x) = lim h(x,n). We say that s is decidable if both s and its complement –s are recursively enumerable.


An extension of such a theory to the general case of the L-subsets is proposed in Gerla (2006) where one refers to the theory of effective domains. It is an open question to give supports for a Church thesis for fuzzy set theory claiming that the proposed notion of recursive enumerability for fuzzy subsets is the adequate one. In Gerla (2001) one proves the following theorem where we refer to fuzzy logics in which a completeness theorem holds true and whose deduction apparatus satisfies some obvious effectiveness property.


Theorem. Any axiomatizable fuzzy theory is recursively enumerable. In particular, the fuzzy set of logically true formulas is recursively enumerable in spite of the fact that Lt is not recursively enumerable, in general. Moreover, any axiomatizable and complete theory is decidable.


It is an open question to use the notion of recursively enumerable fuzzy subset to extend Gödel’s limitative theorems to fuzzy logic.

Paradoxes

The heap paradox

To show an example of approximate reasoning in fuzzy logic we refer to the famous "heap paradox". Let n be a natural number and denote by Small(n) a sentence whose intended meaning is "a heap with n stones is small" (n is a numeral to denote n). Then it is natural to assume the validity of the atomic formula Small(1) and, for every n, the validity of Small(n) → Small(n+1).

On the other hand from these formulas given any natural number n, by applying MP (Modus Ponens) rule several times we can prove that a heap with n stones is small. Indeed,

- from Small(1) and Small(1)→ Small(2) by MP we may state Small(2);

- from Small(2) and Small(2)→ Small(3) by MP we may state Small(3),

- from Small(n-1) and Small(n-1)→ Small(n) by MP we may state Small(n).


Obviously, a conclusion like Small(20.000) is contrary to our intuition in spite of the fact that the reasoning is correct and the premises appear very reasonable. Clearly, the core of such a paradox lies in the vagueness of the predicate " small" and therefore, as proposed by Goguen (1968/69), we can refer to the notion of approximate reasoning to face it. Indeed it is a fact that everyone is convinced that the implications Small(n) → Small(n+1) are very close to the truth but not completely true, in general. We can try to "respect" this conviction by assigning to these formulas a truth value λ very close to 1 but different from 1. Then, for example, we can express the hypothesis of the heap paradox by the following fuzzy theory


Small(1) [to degree 1]

Small(2) [to degree 1]

...

Small(10.000) [to degree 1]

Small(10.000)→ Small(10.001) [to degree λ]

Small(10.001)→ Small(10.002) [to degree λ]

...


In accordance, the Heap Paradox argument can be restated as follows where we denote by λ(n) the n-power of λ with respect to .


Since Small(10.000) [to degree 1]

and Small(10.000)→ Small(10.001) [to degree λ]

we state Small(10.001) [to degree 1λ = λ(1)]

since Small(10.001) [to degree λ]

and Small(10.001)→ Small(10.002) [to degree λ]

we state Small(10.002) [to degree λλ = λ(2) ]

. . .

since Small(10.000+n-1) [to degree λ(n-1)]

and Small(10.000+n-1) → Small(10.000+n) [to degree λ]

we state Small(10.000+n) [to degree λ(n-1)λ = λ(n)].


In particular, we can prove Small(10.000+10.000) at degree λ(10.000) . Now, this is not paradoxical. Indeed if is the Lukasievicz triangular norm, then λ(n) = max {nλ-n+1, 0}. As a consequence, we have that λ(n) = 0 for every n ≥ 1/(1-λ). Assume that λ = 1-10-4 then λ(10.000) = 0. In this way we get a formal representation of heap argument preserving its intuitive content but avoiding its paradoxical character.


The argument on the basis of heap paradox enables us to show an interesting fact:

"the induction principle is not valid in fuzzy logic, i.e. we cannot extend such a principle to vague properties".

In fact, assume that the formula Small(1) → ((n(Small(n) → Small(n+1)) → n Small(n)) is satisfied at degree μ ≠ 0 and let λ ≠ 1 such that λ μ ≠ 0. Then, by two application of MP we can prove n Small(n) to degree λ μ ≠ 0. This contradicts the fact that n Small(n) is false.


The Poincaré paradox

The so called “paradox” of Poincaré refers to indistinguishability by emphasizing that, in spite of common intuition, this relation is not transitive. In fact, let d1,…, dm be a sequence of objects such that we are not able to distinguish di from di+1 and that, nevertheless, that we have no difficulty in distinguishing d1 from dm. Also, consider a first order language with a predicate symbol E to denote the indistinguishability relation and, for every i in N, with a constant ci to denote di. Then it is natural to consider the theory defined by the following formulas:

E(c1,c2),…, E(ci-1,ci),..., E(c1,cm), E(x,z)E(z,y) E(x,y).

From such a theory, by suitable applications of the -introduction rule, particularization and MP, we can prove E(c1,cm) and this contradicts the hypothesis E(c1,cm). Consider a value λ very close to 1 and such that λ(m-1) = 0. Then in fuzzy logic we can formalize Poincaré argument as follows:

Step 1.

Since E(c1,c2) [at degree λ]

and E(c2,c3) [at degree λ]

we can state E(c1,c2)E(c2,c3) [at degree λ(2)].

Therefore, since E(c1,c2)E(c2,c3) E(c1,c3) [at degree 1]

we can state E(c1,c3) [at degree λ(2)].


Step 2.

Since E(c1,c3) [at degree λ(2)]

and E(c3,c4) [at degree λ]

we can state E(c1,c3)E(c3,c4) [at degree λ(3)]

Therefore, since E(c1,c3)E(c3,c4) E(c1,c4) [at degree 1]

we can state E(c1,c4) [at degree λ(3)]

...

Step m-2.

Since E(c1, cm-1) [at degree λ(m-2)]

and E(cm-1,cm) [at degree λ]

we can state E(c1, cm-1)E(cm-1, cm) [at degree λ(m-1)]

Therefore, since E(c1, cm-1)E(cm-1, cm)E(c1, cm) [at degree 1]

we can state E(c1, cm) [at degree λ(m-1)].

Thus, such a proof entails that the conclusion E(c1,cm) is true at least at degree λ(m-1) = 0 (no information). This is not paradoxical.

The liar paradox

(to be included)


Fuzzy logic with no truth-functional semantics

Fuzzy logic extends beyond the truth-functional tradiction of multi-valued logic. The following are two examples.

Necessity logic

This very simple fuzzy logic is obtained by an obvious fuzzyfication of first order classical logic. Indeed, assume, for example, that the deduction apparatus of classical first order logic is presented by a suitable set la of logical axioms, by the MP-rule and the Generalization rule and denote by the related consequence relation. Then a fuzzy deduction system is obtained by considering as fuzzy subset of logical axioms the characteristic function of la and as fuzzy inference rules the extension of MP obtained by assuming that is the minimum operator . Moreover, an extension of the Generalization rule is obtained by assuming that if we prove α at degree λ then we obtain xα(x) at the same degree λ. Assume that D is the deduction operator of such a fuzzy logic and that s is a fuzzy theory. Then D(s)(α) = 1 for every logically true formula α and, otherwise,

.

By recalling that the existential quantifier is interpreted by the supremum operator, such a formula arises from a multivalued valuation of the (metalogical) claim: "α is a consequence of the fuzzy subset s of axioms provided there are formulas in s able to prove "

In such a case the vagueness originates from s, i.e., from the notion of "hypothesis". Moreover is not a truth degree but rather a degree of "preference" or "acceptability" for . For example, let T be a system of axioms for set theory and assume that the choice axiom CA does not depend on T. Then we can consider the fuzzy subset of axioms s defined by setting

s(α) = 1 if α T,

s(α) = 0.8 if α = CA ,

s(α) = 0 otherwise.

A simple calculation shows that:

D(s)(α) = 1 if α is a theorem of T,

D(s)(α) = 0.8 if we cannot prove α from T but α is a theorem of T + CA,

D(s)(α) = 0 otherwise .

Then, despite the fact that no vague predicate is considered in set theory, in the metalanguage we can consider a vague meta-predicate as "is acceptable" and to represent it by a suitable fuzzy subset s.

Similarity logic

In accordance with the ideas of M. S. Ying (1994) we can extend necessity logic by introducing a similarity relation among the predicates (see also Biacino, Gerla, Ying (2002)). As an example, consider an inference like

Since x is a thriller x good for me +

and b is a detective story +

and "detective story" is synonymous of "thriller"

then "b is good for me".

Now the synonymy is a vague notion we can represent by a suitable similarity e in the set W of English worlds, i.e. a fuzzy relation e such that

(a) e(x,x) = 1 (reflexivity), (b) e(x,z) e(z,y) ≤ e(x,y) (transitivity), (c) e(x,y) = e(y,x) (symmetry).

Also, as it is usual in fuzzy logic, it is natural to admit that the truth degree of the conclusion "b is good for me" depends on the degree of similarity between the predicates "detective story" and "thriller", obviously. The structure of the corresponding fuzzy inference rule is:

If α was proven at degree λ

and α’→ β at degree μ

then β is proven at degree λμe(α,α’).

Every inference rule can be extended in a similar way, i.e. by relaxing the precise matching of the identity with the approximate matching of a similarity. These ideas are also on the basis for a similarity-based fuzzy logic programming.


See also

Bibliography

  • Biacino L., Gerla G., Ying M. S.: Approximate reasoning based on similarity, Math. Log. Quart., 46 (2000), 77-86.
  • Chang C. C.,Keisler H. J., Continuous Model Theory, Princeton University Press, Princeton, 1996.
  • Cignoli R., D’Ottaviano I. M. L. , Mundici D. , Algebraic Foundations of Many-Valued Reasoning. Kluwer, Dordrecht, 1999.
  • Elkan C.. The Paradoxical Success of Fuzzy Logic. November 1993. Available from Elkan's home page.
  • Hájek P., Metamathematics of fuzzy logic. Kluwer 1998.
  • Hájek P., Fuzzy logic and arithmetical hierarchy, Fuzzy Sets and Systems, 3, (1995), 359-363.
  • Hájek P., Arithmetical complexity of fuzzy predicate logics – a survey, Soft Computing, 9(2005) 935-941.
  • Hájek P., Novák V., The sorites paradox and fuzzy logic, Internat. J. General Systems, 32 (2003) 373-383.
  • Klir G. and Folger T., Fuzzy Sets, Uncertainty, and Information (1988), ISBN 0-13-345984-5.
  • Klir G. and Bo Yuan, Fuzzy Sets and Fuzzy Logic (1995) ISBN 0-13-101171-5
  • Gerla G., Fuzzy logic: Mathematical Tools for Approximate Reasoning, Kluwer 2001 ISBN 0-7923-6941-6.
  • Gerla G., Effectiveness and Multivalued Logics, Journal of Symbolic Logic, 71 (2006) 137-162.
  • Gottwald S., A treatase on Multi-Valued Logics, Research Studies Press LTD, Baldock 2001.
  • Goguen J. A., The logic of inexact concepts, Synthese, 19 (1968/69) 325-373.
  • Gottwald S., A Treatise on Many-Valued Logics, Studies in Logic and Computation, Research Studies Press, Baldock, 2001.
  • Gottwald S., Mathematical fuzzy logic as a tool for the treatment of vague information, Information Sciences, 72, (2005) 41-1.
  • Montagna F., Three complexity problems in quantified fuzzy logic. Studia Logica, 68(2001) 143-152.
  • Montagna F., On the predicate logic of continuous t-norm BL-algebras, Archive for Math. Logic, 44 (2005) 97-114.
  • Novák V., Perfilieva I, Mockor J., Mathematical Principles of Fuzzy Logic, Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht, (1999).
  • Novák V., Fuzzy logic with countable evaluated syntax revisited, Fuzzy Sets and Systems, 158 (2007) 929-936.
  • Santos E. S., Fuzzy algorithms, Inform. and Control, 17,(1970), 326-339.
  • Pavelka, On fuzzy logic, I-III, Zeitschr. Math. Logik Grundl. Math., 25, (1979), 45-52, 119-134, 447-464.
  • Scarpellini B., Die Nichaxiomatisierbarkeit des unendlichwertigen Prädikatenkalküls von Łukasiewicz, J. of Symbolic Logic, 27,(1962), 159-170.
  • Wiedermann J. , Characterizing the super-Turing computing power and efficiency of classical fuzzy Turing machines, Theor. Comput. Sci. 317, (2004), 61-69.
  • Ying M. S., A logic for approximate reasoning, J. Symbolic Logic, 59 (1994).
  • Zadeh L. A., Fuzzy Sets, Information and Control, 8 (1965) 338­-353.
  • Zadeh L. A., Fuzzy algorithms, Information and Control, 5,(1968), 94-102.
  • Zimmermann H., Fuzzy Set Theory and its Applications (2001), ISBN 0-7923-7435-5.