- “Whatever might be the ultimate goals of some scientists, science, as it is currently practiced, depends on multiple overlapping descriptions of the world, each of which has a domain of applicability. In some cases this domain is very large, but in others quite small.”[52]
- —E.B. Davies: Epistemological pluralism, p. 4
The desiderata of a "good" theory have been debated for centuries, going back perhaps even earlier than Occam's razor,[53] which often is taken as an attribute of a good theory. Occam's razor might fall under the heading of "elegance", the first item on the list, but too zealous an application was cautioned by Einstein: "Everything should be made as simple as possible, but no simpler."[54]
Thomas Kuhn argued that changes in scientists' views of reality not only contain subjective elements, but result from group dynamics, "revolutions" in scientific practice and changes in "paradigms".[55] As an example, Kuhn suggested that the Sun-centric Copernican "revolution" replaced the Earth-centric views of Ptolemy not because of empirical failures, but because of a new "paradigm" that exerted control over what scientists felt to be the more fruitful way to pursue their goals (Colyvan's requirement of "fruitfulness").
Whatever criteria one adopts for a 'good' theory, Worrall says the question of an objective algorithm for theory choice at the moment leaves open the question of what exactly it is rational or irrational to do. "One reason that these criteria do not supply [constitute] a choice algorithm is that, in live [ongoing] cases of theory choice, and particularly during scientific revolutions, these different criteria seldom, if ever, tell in the same direction [all point the same way]."[56] (Wording in [...] brackets added). In other words, although these criteria assist in identifying a 'good' theory, the selection among theories still is a subjective matter that will lead to different choices depending upon who is the judge.
The environment of scientific practice has been described as including some hypothetical and subjective aspects, namely:[57]
- The reality principle; We have to content ourselves with "things-as-they-appear", not 'reality'.
- The fact principle; Facts are not theory-neutral. Observation is not possible without reference to a theory.
- The theory principle; The process of abstraction from facts to theories is complex and intuitive, and any approach is valid if it leads to a theory that works.
- The testability principle; A scientific theory should be testable through reference to facts, although tests are rarely decisive.
- The veracity principle; Acceptance of a theory involves many factors: simplicity, efficacy, utility, explanatory power and human measures such as beauty.
- The Copernican principle; The universe is not organized for our benefit and we are not uniquely privileged observers.
To what extent our mental creations are limited by the innate functioning of our brain/nervous system (what might be called our "factory settings") and to what extent they mirror the real world is discussed in the field of psychological nativism, and is connected with the philosophers Kant, Schopenhauer, Popper, Chomsky, Pinker, Hawking and others.[58]
Complementary descriptions
The subjective and objective correlates of some phenomena (like addiction or mental disorder) actually might describe the same phenomena from distinct perspectives; in other words, they might be complementary views:
- ...for each individual there is one 'mental life' but two ways of knowing it: first-person knowledge and third-person knowledge. From a first-person perspective conscious experiences appear causally effective. From a third person perspective the same causal sequence can be explained in neural terms. It is not the case that the view from one perspective is right and the other wrong. These perspectives are complementary. The differences between how things appear from a first-person versus a third-person perspective has to do with differences in the observational arrangements (the means by which a subject and an external observer access the subject's mental processes)."[59]
- —Max Velmans: How could conscious experiences affect brains?, p. 11
|
Niels Bohr also believed there were differences between first-person and third-person perspectives, an outgrowth of his experience in atomic physics. However, in his view the two descriptions are irreconcilable because of the disturbance of the subject's first-person mental state by the third-person's act of observation itself:
- "...On the contrary, the recognition of the limitation of mechanical concepts in atomic physics would rather seem suited to conciliate the apparently contrasting viewpoints of physiology [that is, neuroscience] and psychology [mental phenomena]. Indeed, the necessity of considering the interaction between the measuring instruments and the object under investigation in atomic mechanics exhibits a close analogy to the peculiar difficulties in psychological analysis arising from the fact that the mental content is invariably altered when the attention is concentrated on any special feature of it."[60]
- —Niels Bohr: Light and Life
|
Some weak indirect support for this analogy is found in observations of the neural correlates of mental states:
- "...it is important to be clear about exactly what experience one wants one's subjects to introspect. Of course, explaining to subjects exactly what the experimenter wants them to experience can bring its own problems–...instructions to attend to a particular internally generated experience can easily alter both the timing and he content of that experience and even whether or not it is consciously experienced at all."[61]
- —Susan Pockett: The neuroscience of movement
|
Antireductionism
The above discussion shows the uneasy relation between the subjective and the objective, and attempts to reconcile the two continue:
- "The great advances in the physical and biological sciences were made possible by excluding the mind from the physical world. ..But at some point it will be necessary to make a new start on a more comprehensive understanding that includes the mind"[62]
- —Thomas Nagel: Mind and Cosmos: Why the Materialist Neo-Darwinian Conception of Nature Is Almost Certainly False, p. 8
|
- "In recent years, however, it has become increasingly clear to many researchers that cognitive science is incomplete. ..a complete science of the mind needs to account for subjectivity and consciousness."[63]
- —Evan Thompson: Mind in Life: Biology, Phenomenology, and the Sciences of Mind, p. 3
|
- "The investigations of science have proved beyond all doubt that there is no fact which exists in pure isolation, but that every experience, however objective it may seem, inevitably becomes enveloped in a complex of assumptions as soon as the scientist attempts to express it in a formula. But while this aura of subjective interpretation may remain imperceptible where the field of observation is limited, it is bound to become practically dominant as soon as the field of vision extends to the whole."[64]
- —Pierre Teilhard de Chardin: The Phenomenon of Man, p. 30
|
The basis of 'objectivity' has been sought in raw perception:
- "The entire universe of science is constructed upon the lived world, and if we wish to think about science rigorously, to appreciate precisely its sense and scope, we must first awaken that experience of the world of which science is the second-order expression. Science neither has, nor ever will have, the same ontological sense as the perceived world for the simple reason that science is a determination or an explanation of that world."[65]
- — Maurice Merleau-Ponty: The Phenomenology of Perception Preface: p. xxii
|
while others have pointed out that "raw perception" is influenced by preconceptions:[66]
- "There is a sense in which seeing is a 'theory-laden' undertaking."
- – Norwood Russell Hanson, Patterns of Discovery: An Inquiry into the Conceptual Foundations of Science p. 21
|
Some authors look to science to ultimately include the whole picture, hoping that a more complete understanding of complex feedback systems and emergence will bring subjectivity within science.[67] Others look to the evolution of religion to expand the understanding of man and his place in the universe.[64] Still others look to a clear recognition of the limitations of science to open our minds to a different type of understanding altogether.[62]
- "The separateness of physical science, and its claim to completeness, has to end in the long run. And that poses the question: To what extent will the reductive form that is so central to contemporary physical science survive this transformation? If physics and chemistry cannot fully account for life and consciousness, how will their immense body of truth be combined with other elements in an expanded conception of the natural order that can accommodate these things?"[62]
- —Thomas Nagel: Mind and Cosmos: Why the Materialist Neo-Darwinian Conception of Nature Is Almost Certainly False, p. 8
|
These ideas still are under examination. Aside from antireductionism, which sometimes is restricted to be only a technical argument about levels of abstraction,[68][69] other modern attempts to develop the subject are the philosophical fields of enactivism and embodied cognition,[70] and the scientific fields of cognitive psychology, behavioral genetics and evolutionary psychology.
In early philosophy
The question of what is objective and what is subjective, and whether one or the other is more "real" has been a topic of philosophy since its earliest days. In Western philosophy it can be found in Plato, who considered our perceptions to be mere approximations to the world of ideal Forms, in the way that circles we encounter in nature are mere approximations to the ideal circle. The world of Forms was accessible only by the mind, not the senses. Contrary views were held by Aristotle, who would hold the "ideal" circle is only an abstraction from its many real-world examples, and without those examples the ideal circle simply would not exist. See this discussion about "instantiation", whether 'properties' are universals or particulars. These two views of how the concepts of the mind relate to the perception of the world resurface again and again in later centuries, rephrased in novel terminologies.
Some of these later treatments of the subject-object relationship were tied to theological issues. A not-so-serious example is the question "If a tree fall in the forest, and no one is around to hear it, does it make a sound?"[71] Although not the originator of this exact question, George Berkeley (1685-1753) proposed that objects (and trees specifically) exist only when perceived by a conscious being, and to avoid the absurdities of this view posited that because God was omnipresent, things existed because they were in His consciousness.[72]
- There once was a man who said 'God
- Must think it exceedingly odd
- If he finds that this tree
- Continues to be
- When there's no one about in the Quad.'
- Dear Sir: Your astonishment's odd:
- I am always about in the Quad.
- And that's why the tree
- Will continue to be
- Since observed by yours faithfully, God.
- —Twentieth century limerick quoted by Nigel Warburton: A Little History of Philosophy, p. 91[72]
|
According to a famous anecdote, Samuel Johnson responded to Berkeley's views by kicking a stone and saying 'I refute it thus ', a refutation Boswell took to illustrate that Johnson's genius could be profitably applied to philosophical matters.[73] One might argue that Johnson's experiment instances Berkeley's point: the stone existed because Johnson became aware of it, and kicking it only enhanced Johnson's awareness. In any event, Berkeley is correct within the interpretation that all we can know of reality is our perceptions of it.
Berkeley's view is summarized in the Latin phrase: Esse est percipi, to be is to be perceived. A similar view predating Berkeley was proposed by Spinoza (1632-1677), who held that "every particular thing or being is a modification of the infinite substance i.e. of God. It expresses itself by each of his attributes, in particular that of extension and that of thought...to Spinoza any inanimate bodily thing is at the same time also ‘a thought of God’"[74] This idea is expressed in the Jesuit admonition to "find God in all things" (a maxim of Ignatius of Loyola put forth in his Exercises of 1548[75]) and is carried to a modern perspective by Pierre Teilhard de Chardin with the concept of the noosphere, "a thinking layer containing the collective consciousness of humanity which will envelope the earth"[76] and the idea that "the old conception of matter and mind be replaced with a new notion of “matter-spirit”. The noosphere is the culmination of the evolution of consciousness (which is a continuation of biological evolution)."[77][78] "We must infer the presence of potential mind in all material systems, by backward extrapolation from the human phase to the biological, and from the biological to the inorganic."[79]
In 18th and 19th century philosophy
To say it simply, Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) pointed out that we all shape our experience of things through the filter of our mind. The mind shapes that experience, and among other things, Kant believed the concepts of space and time were programmed into the human brain, as was the notion of cause and effect.[80] We never have direct experience of things, the noumenal world, and what we do experience is the phenomenal world as conveyed by our senses, this conveyance processed by the machinery of the mind and nervous system. Kant focused upon this processing. Kant believed in a priori knowledge arrived at independent of experience, so-called synthetic a priori knowledge. In particular, he thought that by introspection some aspects of the filtering mechanisms of the mind/brain/nervous system could be discovered.[80] These observations summarize Kant's views upon the subject-object problem, called Kant's Copernican revolution. It was the inversion of the traditional relation between the observing subject and the outer object of knowledge:
- "It has hitherto been assumed that our cognition must conform to the objects; but all attempts to ascertain anything about these objects a priori, by means of conceptions, and thus to extend the range of our knowledge, have been rendered abortive by this assumption. Let us then make the experiment whether we may not be more successful in metaphysics, if we assume that the objects must conform to our cognition. This appears, at all events, to accord better with the possibility of our gaining the end we have in view, that is to say, of arriving at the cognition of objects a priori, of determining something with respect to these objects, before they are given to us. We here propose to do just what Copernicus did in attempting to explain the celestial movements. When he found that he could make no progress by assuming that all the heavenly bodies revolved round the spectator, he reversed the process, and tried the experiment of assuming that the spectator revolved, while the stars remained at rest. We may make the same experiment with regard to the intuition of objects."[81]
- —Immanuel Kant: English translation by J. M. D. Meiklejohn of The Critique of Pure Reason 1781
Kant's successors Fichte (1762-1814), Schelling ( 1775-1854) and Hegel (1770-1831) also raised the issue of the relationship between the subject and the object, or what perceives and what is perceived, and stressed the importance of the subject, the observer. Fichte placed the demands of the individual self or ego as the starting point of all philosophical reflection. He transformed Kant's view, that the laws of rationality are set by forms of human understanding, instead into demands of the individual will.[82] Hegel also rejected Kant's view that there was a noumenal world causing our experiences and instead proposed that the mind-shaped phenomenal world is the world. Hegel proposed that 'truth' was approached by a dialectical method, that is, a clash of an idea and its opposite, a succession of thesis and antithesis, followed by a synthesis of the two, and on, and on, a picture he felt described the evolution of history in an ever-upward spiral to 'truth'.[83] Although a popular figure, many other philosophers found Hegel unintelligible, with Bertrand Russell suggesting Hegel's work as a model of the imprecise use of language, and A.J. Ayer declaring that most of Hegel's sentences said nothing at all.[83]
Schopenhauer (1788-1860) claimed that “everything that exists for knowledge, and hence the whole of this world, is only object in relation to the subject, perception of the perceiver, in a word, representation.”[84] According to him there can be "No object without subject" because "everything objective is already conditioned as such in manifold ways by the knowing subject with the forms of its knowing, and presupposes these forms; consequently it wholly disappears when the subject is thought away.".[85] Schopenhauer also asserted that the 'principle of sufficient reason' does not apply between subject and object, but only between objects. Therefore, Fichte was mistaken when he posited that the subject produces or causes the object.[85] Realism and Materialism also are wrong when they assert that the object causes the subject.[86]
In 20th and 21st century philosophy
In his lecture "Mind and Matter," Erwin Schrödinger stressed the distancing of the knowing subject from its 'objective' formulation of the world around us:
- "By this I mean the thing that is so frequently called the 'hypothesis of the real world' around us. I maintain that it amounts to certain simplifications which we adopt in order to master the infinitely intricate problem of nature. Without being aware of it... we exclude the Subject of Cognizance [knowing subject] from the domain of nature that we endeavor to understand. We step with our own person back into the part of an onlooker who does not belong to the world, which by this very procedure becomes an objective world."[87]
- —Erwin Schrödinger: Mind and Matter
|
He claimed that we are unaware "of the fact that a moderately satisfying picture of the world has only been reached at the high price of taking ourselves out of the picture, stepping back into the role of a non-concerned observer."[87] As a result, in formulating the concept of the object, the subject is not considered at all. Schrödinger continues:
- "So we are faced with the following remarkable situation. While the stuff from which our world picture is built is yielded exclusively from the sense organs as organs [that is, agents] of the mind, so that every man's world picture is and always remains a construct of the mind and cannot be proved to have any other existence, yet the conscious mind itself remains a stranger within that construct, it has no living space in it, you can spot it nowhere in space...To learn that it [the personality of a human being] cannot really be found there [in the interior of a human body] is so amazing that it meets with doubts and hesitation, we are very loath to admit it."[87]
- —Erwin Schrödinger: Mind and Matter
|
These observations are supplemented by those of Northoff mentioned above.[17]
The knowing subject can be brought into the discussion by considering how it colors its own observations. As stated by Schopenhauer:
- " ‘ The world is my representation: ’ — this is a truth which holds good for everything that lives and knows, though man alone can bring it into reflective and abstract consciousness. If he really does this, he has attained to philosophical wisdom. It then becomes clear and certain to him that he does not know a sun and an earth, but only an eye that sees a sun, a hand that feels an earth; that the world which surrounds him is there only as representation, in other words, only in reference to another thing, the consciousness, which is himself."[88]
- —Arthur Schopenhauer: The World as Will and Representation, p. 3
|
The role of the 'knowing subject' involves its limitations. Of course, language is indispensable in the formulation and communication of our perceptions of the objective world, as was pointed out by Wittgenstein:
- "The main point is the theory of what can be expressed (gesagt) by propositions — i.e. by language (and, what comes to the same, what can be thought) and what cannot be expressed by propositions, but only shown (gezeigt) [manifested in a non-verbal way]; which, I believe, is the cardinal problem of philosophy."[89]
- —Ludwig Wittgenstein; quoted by Russell Nieli, p. 113 [...] is paraphrase by Nieli, p. 163
|
Chomsky and Pinker have taken this idea further back than languages that are actually in use, to a question of how the brain itself functions:
- "People do not think in English or Chinese or Apache; they think in a language of thought. This language of thought probably looks a bit like all these languages;...But compared with any given language, mentalese must be richer in some ways and simpler in others."[90]
- —Steven Pinker: The Language Instinct, p. 72
|
Thus, like Kant, Chomsky and Pinker raise the issue of the mind's inherent programming. Chomsky selected as a particular example the acquiring of language by children.[58] Chomsky marshaled evidence that a child's rapid mastery of the complexity of language indicated an innate ability programmed into the development of the human mind from birth that could not be explained by the "blank slate" view of the infant mind. Rather, the mind has a built-in propensity to process symbolic representations. The origins of this ability were sought by Pinker in a Darwinian struggle that established the survival value of the ability to communicate.[91] According to Pinker, Charles Darwin himself "concluded that language ability is 'an instinctive tendency to acquire an art', a design that is not peculiar to humans but seen in other species such as song-learning birds."
References
- ↑
Hyslop, Alec (Jan 14, 2014). Edward N. Zalta, ed:Other Minds. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2015 Edition). Retrieved on 2016-02-17.
- ↑
Simon Blackburn (1996). “Enchanting views”, Bob Hale, Peter Clark, eds: Reading Putnam. Wiley-Blackwell, 14. ISBN 978-0631199953. On-line accessible using this link to Amazon's "look inside" feature.
- ↑
J. E. Malpas (1992). Donald Davidson and the Mirror of Meaning: Holism, Truth, Interpretation. Cambridge University Press Archive, pp. 191 ff. ISBN 052141721X.
- ↑
Max Velmans (2009). Understanding Consciousness, 2nd. Taylor & Francis, p. 3. ISBN 0415425158.
- ↑
Oliver Sacks. Musicophilia: Tales of Music and the Brain, Revised and enlarged ed. Vintage, p. 265. ISBN 978-1400033539.
- ↑
Quote from Spinoza's Ethics by Evald Vasilyevich Ilyenkov (2008). Dialectical Logic; Essays on its History and Theory. Aakar Books, pp. 66-67. ISBN 9788189833398.
- ↑
Gerald Maurice Edelman (2001). “Building a picture of the brain”, Gerald M. Edelman, Jean-Pierre Changeux, eds: The Brain, Augmented version of an issue of Daedalus, Spring 1998 ed. Transaction Publishers, p. 56. ISBN 9781412836067.
- ↑
Paul Craddock (2009). Scientific Investigation of Copies, Fakes and Forgeries. Routledge, pp. 22,23. ISBN 9781136436024.
- ↑
This much-used quotation is overwhelmingly attributed to Henri Bergson. Although it captures Bergson's views, there is no evidence that it is a translation of anything Bergson wrote. There is no doubt, however, that this sentence appears verbatim in Robertson Davies (2009). Tempest-Tost. Penguin Group (CA), p. 107. ISBN 0143054910. Translations of three major works by Bergson can be found at the Mead Project: Matter and Memory, Creative Evolution and Time and Free Will.
- ↑
For an extensive discussion of the origins of this quotation, often attributed to Anaïs Nin, see Garson O’Toole:"We don't see things...". Quote Investigator. Retrieved on August 2, 2016.
- ↑
Elizabeth Styles (2006). “Inattentional blindness”, The Psychology of Attention, 2nd ed.. Psychology Press, pp. 266 ff. ISBN 0203968212.
- ↑
Paul Ricoeur (1995). Oneself as another, Kathleen Blamey, translator. University of Chicago Press, pp. 1 ff. ISBN 0226713296.
- ↑
Walter Mischel, Carolyn C Morf (2003). “Chapter 2: The self as a psycho-social dynamic processing system: A meta-perspective on a century of the self in psychology”, Mark R Leary, June Price Tangney: Handbook of self and identity. Guilford Press, pp. 15 ff. ISBN 1572307986.
- ↑
This idea is a generalization of the claim of completeness of physical theory, the notion that the physical sciences provide sufficient causes for all events. See for example, Jens Harbecke (2008). Mental Causation: Investigating the Mind's Powers in a Natural World. Ontos Verlag, p. 214. ISBN 3938793945.
- ↑
This quote is from: Eric R. Kandel (2007). In Search of Memory: The Emergence of a New Science of Mind. WW Norton, p. 9. ISBN 0393329372. However, the same language can be found in dozens of sources. Some philosophers object to the unsupported statement of such conjectures, for example, observing that consciousness has yet to be shown to be a process at all, never mind a biological process. See Oswald Hanfling (2002). Wittgenstein and the Human Form of Life. Psychology Press, pp. 108-109. ISBN 0415256453.
- ↑
Thomas Nagel (1989). The View from Nowhere. Oxford University Press, pp. 6-7. ISBN 9780195056440.
- ↑ 17.0 17.1
A rather extended discussion is provided in Georg Northoff (2004). Philosophy of the Brain: The Brain Problem, Volume 52 of Advances in Consciousness Research. John Benjamins Publishing. ISBN 1588114171.
- ↑
Eric R. Kandel (2007). In Search of Memory: The Emergence of a New Science of Mind. WW Norton, p. 382. ISBN 0393329372.
- ↑
Ernest Nagel (1999). “§V: Alternative descriptions of physical state”, The Structure of Science: Problems in the Logic of Scientific Explanation, 2nd. Hackett, pp. 285-292. ISBN 0915144719.
- ↑
For example, see Three Worlds by Karl Popper - The Tanner Lecture on Human Values - Delivered by Karl Popper at The University of Michigan on April 7, 1978.
- ↑
For example, Stephen Hawking has proposed that reality is a patchwork of overlapping theoretical models each representing a different slice of experience with its own concepts and supporting observations, a model-dependent realism. See his book with Leonard Mlodinow: Leonard Mlodinow, Stephen Hawking (2010). “Chapter 1: The mystery of being”, The grand design, p. 9. ISBN 0553805371.
- ↑
A proponent of this analogy is Shimon Edelman (2008). Computing the Mind: How the Mind Really Works. Oxford University Press. ISBN 0195320670. Google books link.
- ↑
Silvan S. Schweber (1994). QED and the men who made it: Dyson, Feynman, Schwinger, and Tomonaga. Princeton University Press, p. 465. ISBN 0691033277. A more technical description is provided by Adrian Wüthrich (2010). The Genesis of Feynman Diagrams. Springer, p. 9. ISBN 9048192277.
- ↑
Aaron Copland (1980). “The Charles Elliot Norton lectures, 1951-52”, Music and Imagination. Harvard University Press, p. 10. ISBN 0674589157. “It [music] is at the same time outside and away from us and inside and part of us.”
- ↑
David Swartz (1998). “The subjective/objective antimony”, Culture and Power: The Sociology of Pierre Bourdieu, 2nd. University of Chicago Press, p. 55. ISBN 0226785955.
- ↑
Alec Rogers (2012). “The division between subjective and objective defines life”, Cognitive Set Theory. ArborRhythms, p. 85. ISBN 0983037604.
- ↑
"A young school teacher John Thomas Scopes was prosecuted for teaching evolution in class, in defiance of a state law prohibiting such teaching. Prosecuted by three-times presidential candidate William Jennings Bryan and defended by noted agnostic lawyer Clarence Darrow, the ‘Scopes Monkey Trial’ caught the attention of the world" See Ruse, Michael (Jun 6, 2014). Edward N. Zalta (ed.):Creationism. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2014 Edition).
- ↑
David Hurst Thomas (2000). The Skull Wars: Kennewick man, archaeology, and the battle for Native American identity. Basic Books. ISBN 9780786724369.
- ↑
Lee Smolin (2006). “Chapter 16: How do you fight sociology?”, The Trouble with Physics: The Rise of String Theory, the Fall of a Science, and What Comes Next. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt, pp. 261 ff. ISBN 061891868X.
- ↑
Peter Woit (2006). “Chapter 16: The only game in town: the power and the glory of string theory”, Not even wrong: the failure of string theory and the search for unity in physical law. Basic Books, pp. 221 ff. ISBN 0465092756.
- ↑
Ralph Eugene Lapp (1965). The new priesthood;: The scientific elite and the uses of power. Harper & Row. and Spencer Klaw (1968). The new brahmins; scientific life in America. William Morrow. ISBN 0688021611.
- ↑
Jacob Needleman. The Heart of Philosophy, Penguin paperback reprint of Alfred A Knopf 1982 ed, p. 210. ISBN 1585422517.
- ↑
Lewis Mumford (1974). “Chapter 3 §2: The Crime of Galileo”, The Myth of the Machine - Book 2: The Pentagon of Power. Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, p. 57. ISBN 9780156716109.
- ↑
William James (1886). “The dilemma of determinism”, The Will to Believe: And Other Essays in Popular Philosophy, Reprint. Longmans, Green, and Company, 145 ff. On-line text here An address to Harvard Divinity School students in Divinity Hall on March 13, 1884.
- ↑
John Martin Fischer (2011). “Chapter 4: Indeterminism and control: An approach to the problem of luck”, Law and Neuroscience: Current Legal Issues. Oxford University Press, pp. 41-60. ISBN 019959984X. Also published in John Martin Fischer (2012). “Chapter 6: Indeterminism and control: An approach to the problem of luck”, Deep Control: Essays on Free Will and Value. Oxford University Press, pp. 85 ff. ISBN 0199742987. On-line version available from University of Oklahoma.
- ↑
Ted J Kaptchuk (2002). "The placebo effect in alternative medicine: can the performance of a healing ritual have clinical significance?". Annals of Internal Medicine 136 (11): pp. 817-825.
- ↑
David R Soderquist (2002). Sensory Processes. SAGE, p. 110. ISBN 0761923330. “Pain is always subjective”
- ↑
Christopher A. Cavacuiti (2012). Principles of Addiction Medicine: The Essentials. Lippincott Williams & Wilkins. ISBN 1451153600. “The landmark positron emission tomography (PET) scan findings of Volkow et al., obtained from cocaine-addicted human volunteers, have shown that dopamine in the dorsal striatum is involved in cocaine craving and addiction...the dorsal striatum, therefore, is a high-interest area for studies of of possible transitions from cravings to revulsion.”
- ↑
Nora D Volkow, Joanna S Fowler, and Gene-Jack Wang (2007). “The addicted human brain: insights from imaging studies”, Andrew R Marks and Ushma S Neill, eds: Science In Medicine: The JCI Textbook Of Molecular Medicine. Jones & Bartlett Learning, pp. 1061 ff. ISBN 0763750832.
- ↑
Initially, many refused to believe the results of the telescope. Kepler wrote to Galileo that such persons were "stuck in a world of paper" , blind not by force of circumstance but of their own foolish will. Dan Hofstadter (2009). “Chapter 2: The telescope; or seeing”, The Earth Moves: Galileo and the Roman Inquisition. W W Norton & Co, pp. 53 ff. ISBN 978-0-393-06650-0.
- ↑
There is an entire literature on how to interpret observations with the microscope, and even in the 19th century doubts remained. See, for example, Oliver Goldsmith (1828). A History of the Earth & Animated Nature: In Three Volumes ..., Volume 1. J. F. Dove, p. 229. “These, and many other objections, have been made to this system; which, instead of enlightening the mind, serve only to shew, that too close a pursuit of nature very often leads to uncertainty.”
- ↑ 42.0 42.1
Eric Oberheim, Paul Hoyningen-Huene (Mar 5, 2013). Edward N. Zalta, ed.:The Incommensurability of Scientific Theories. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2013 Edition).
- ↑
Julian Reiss, Jan Sprenger (Aug 25, 2014). Edward N. Zalta (ed.):Scientific Objectivity. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2014 Edition). “Galilei's telescopes were unreliable for celestial observations, and many well-established phenomena (no fixed star parallax, invariance of laws of motion) could at first not be explained in the heliocentric system.”
- ↑
Thomas Kuhn formally stated this need for the "norms for rational theory choice". One of his discussions is reprinted in Thomas S Kuhn. “Chapter 9: Rationality and Theory Choice”, James Conant, John Haugeland, eds: The Road since Structure: Philosophical Essays, 1970-1993,, 2nd. University of Chicago Press, pp. 208 ff. ISBN 0226457990.
- ↑ 45.0 45.1
Mark Colyvan (2001). The Indispensability of Mathematics. Oxford University Press, pp. 78-79. ISBN 0195166612.
- ↑ 46.0 46.1
Stephen Hawking, Leonard Mlodinow (2010). “What is reality?”, The Grand Design. Random House Digital, Inc. ISBN 0553907077. See also: model-dependent realism.
- ↑
Bird, Alexander (Aug 11, 2011). Edward N. Zalta, ed:Thomas Kuhn. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2013 Edition). “Despite the possibility of divergence, there is nonetheless widespread agreement on the desirable features of a new puzzle-solution or theory. Kuhn (1977, 321–2) identifies five characteristics that provide the shared basis for a choice of theory: 1. accuracy; 2. consistency (both internal and with other relevant currently accepted theories); 3. scope (its consequences should extend beyond the data it is required to explain); 4. simplicity (organizing otherwise confused and isolated phenomena); 5. fruitfulness (for further research).” Bird's reference is to Thomas S Kuhn (1977). The Essential Tension. Selected Studies in Scientific Tradition and Change, 7th. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 0226458067.
- ↑
Karl Raimund Popper (2002). The logic of scientific discovery, Reprint of translation of 1935 Logik der Forchung. Routledge/Taylor & Francis Group, pp. 18, 280. ISBN 0415278430.
- ↑
(1979) “Objectivity, value judgment and theory choice”, The Essential Tension: Selected Studies in Scientific Tradition and Change. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 0226458067.
- ↑
Bird, Alexander (Aug 11, 2011). Edward N. Zalta, ed:§4.1 Methodological Incommensurability. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2013 Edition). “They [such criteria] cannot determine scientific choice. First, which features of a theory satisfy these criteria may be disputable (e.g. does simplicity concern the ontological commitments of a theory or its mathematical form?). Secondly, these criteria are imprecise, and so there is room for disagreement about the degree to which they hold. Thirdly, there can be disagreement about how they are to be weighted relative to one another, especially when they conflict.”
- ↑
See Stephen Hawking, Leonard Mlodinow (2010). The Grand Design. Random House Digital, Inc. ISBN 0553907077. “It is a whole family of different theories, each of which is a good description of observations only in some range of physical situations...But just as there is no map that is a good representation of the earth's entire surface, there is no single theory that is a good representation of observations in all situations.”
- ↑
E Brian Davies (2006). Epistemological pluralism. PhilSci Archive.
- ↑
Occam's razor, sometimes referred to as "ontological parsimony", is roughly stated as: Given a choice between two theories, the simplest is the best. This suggestion commonly is attributed to William of Ockham in the 14th-century, although it probably predates him. See Baker, Alan (February 25, 2010). Simplicity; §2: Ontological parsimony. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2011 Edition). Retrieved on 2011-11-14.
- ↑
This quote may be a paraphrase. See MobileReference (2011). Famous Quotes from 100 Great People. MobileReference. ISBN 1611980763. MobilReference is a Boston-based e-book publisher.
- ↑
Thomas S Kuhn (1966). The structure of scientific revolutions, 3rd. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 0226458083.
- ↑
John Worrall (1990). “Scientific revolutions and scientific rationality: the case of the "elderly holdout"”, C Wade Savage, ed: Scientific theories, Volume 14. University of Minnesota Press, 332-333. ISBN 0816618011.
- ↑
Jim Baggott (2013). “Putting theories to test”, Farewell to reality. Pegasus Books, pp. 17-20. ISBN 9781605984728.
- ↑ 58.0 58.1
For a review of recent developments, see for example Samet, Jerry and Zaitchik, Deborah, (Aug 29, 2014). Edward N. Zalta (ed.):Innateness and Contemporary Theories of Cognition. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2014 Edition).
- ↑
Max Velmans (2002). "How Could Conscious Experiences Affect Brains?". Journal of Consciousness Studies 9 (11): pp. 2-29.
- ↑
Niels Bohr (April 1, 1933). "Light and Life". Nature: pp. 457 ff.
Full text on line at us.archive.org.
- ↑
Susan Pockett (2009). “The neuroscience of movement”, Susan Pockett, WP Banks, Shaun Gallagher, eds: Does Consciousness Cause Behavior?. MIT Press, p. 19. ISBN 0262512572.
- ↑ 62.0 62.1 62.2
Thomas Nagel (2012). Mind and Cosmos: Why the Materialist Neo-Darwinian Conception of Nature Is Almost Certainly False. Oxford University Press, p. 8. ISBN 978-0199919758.
- ↑
Evan Thompson (2007). Mind in Life: Biology, Phenomenology, and the Sciences of Mind. Harvard University Press, p. 3. ISBN 9780674025110.
- ↑ 64.0 64.1
Pierre Teilhard de Chardin (2008). The Phenomenon of Man, Reprint of 1965 revised translation. Harper Collins, p. 16. ISBN 9780061632655.
- ↑
Maurice Merleau-Ponty (2013). “Preface”, Phenomenology of Perception, Translation by Donald A Landes of 1945 ed. Routledge, p. xxii. ISBN 9781135718602.
- ↑
Norwood Russell Hanson (1958). Patterns of Discovery: An Inquiry into the Conceptual Foundations of Science. Cambridge University Press, p. 19. ISBN 978-0521092616.
- ↑
Evan Thompson (2007). “Appendix B: Emergence and the problem of downward causation”, Mind in Life: Biology, Phenomenology, and the Sciences of Mind. Harvard University Press, pp. 417 ff. ISBN 9780674025110.
- ↑
Jordi Cat (May 16, 2013). Edward N. Zalta, ed:The Unity of Science: §3.2 Antireductionism. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2013 Edition),.
- ↑
Patricia Churchill (1992). “Chapter 11: Reductionism and antireductionism in functionalist theories of mind”, Brian Beakley, Peter Ludlow, eds: The Philosophy of Mind: Classical Problems/contemporary Issues. MIT Press, pp. 59 ff. ISBN 9780262521673.
- ↑
Robert A Wilson, Lucia Foglia (Jul 25, 2011). Edward N. Zalta, ed):Embodied Cognition. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2011 Edition).
- ↑
Berman has indicated that Galileo answered this question as "no". From a scientific viewpoint, the pressure waves generated by the falling tree do not have the property of "sound". Sound is an interpretation of the vibration of the ear's tympanic membrane, and therefore sound is a perception requiring a listening subject. See Bob Berman (2014). “Chapter 15: Barriers of light and sound”, Zoom: How Everything Moves: From Atoms and Galaxies to Blizzards and Bees. Little, Brown and Company. ISBN 978-0316217408.
- ↑ 72.0 72.1
Nigel Warburton (2011). “Chapter 15: The elephant in the room: George Berkeley (and John Locke)”, A Little History of Philosophy. Yale University Press, pp. 87 ff. ISBN 9780300152081.
- ↑
Boswell, James (1859). The Life of Samuel Johnson, Volume 1. Routledge, Warne, and Routledge, p. 273.
- ↑
Quote from a summary by Erwin Schrödinger (2012). “The physical basis of consciousness”, Forward by Roger Penrose: What is Life?: With Mind and Matter and Autobiographical Sketches. Cambridge University Press, pp. 93-94. ISBN 1107604664.
- ↑
"The third, to consider how God works and labors for me in all things...giving them being, preserving them, giving them vegetation and sensation, etc. Then to reflect on myself." Saint Ignatius (1914). The Spiritual Exercises of St. Ignatius of Loyola, Translation by Elder Mullan. P. J. Kennedy & Sons, Printers.
- ↑
John G Messerly (2012). The Search for Meaning in Life: Religious, Philosophical, Transhumanist and Scientific Perspectives. McGraw-Hill Education. ISBN 9780697813145. For an on-line excerpt concerning Chardin, see John Wesserly (February 23, 2014). Pierre Teilhard de Chardin: Universal Progressive Evolution. The meaning of life: philosophy, evolution, and transhumanism.
- ↑
William Seager, Sean Allen-Hermanson (Aug 23, 2010). Edward N. Zalta, ed:Panpsychism. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2013 Edition).
- ↑
Brennan R. Hill (1998). Christian Faith and the Environment: Making Vital Connections. Orbis Books, p. 247. ISBN 9781556353178.
- ↑
Pierre Teilhard de Chardin (2008). “Introduction by Sir Julian Huxley”, The Phenomenon of Man, Reprint of 1965 revised translation. Harper Collins, p. 16. ISBN 9780061632655.
- ↑ 80.0 80.1
Nigel Warburton (2011). “Chapter 19: Rose-tinted reality: Immanuel Kant”, A little history of philosophy. Yale University Press, pp. 111 ff. ISBN 0300152086.
- ↑
An on-line translation is found at Immanuel Kant. Critique of Pure Reason. Philosophy on the EServer, Iowa State University(eserver.org). Retrieved on 2013-01-16. This and other web resources for Kant are posted by Steve Palmquist, Hong Kong Baptist University.
- ↑
Henry D Aiken (1957). “Egoism in German Philosophy: Johann Gottlieb Fichte”, The Age of Ideology, volume 5 of The Great Ages of Western Philosophy. George Braziller, Inc, pp. 51 ff.
- ↑ 83.0 83.1
Nigel Warburton (2011). “Chapter 22: The owl of Minerva:: Georg W.F. Hegel”, A Little History of Philosophy. Yale University Press, pp. 126 ff. ISBN 9780300152081.
- ↑
Arthur Schopenhauer (1958). The World as Will and Representation, vol. I, E.F.J. Payne translation of Die Welt als Wille und Vorsetellung 1819. Courier Dover Publications, p. 3. ISBN 0486217612. The version translated by Haldane and Kemp is available on line at The world as will and idea. The Internet Archive. Retrieved on 2013-01-11.
- ↑ 85.0 85.1 ….The World as Will and Representation, vol. I, p. 13
- ↑ ….The World as Will and Representation, vol. I, p. 34
- ↑ 87.0 87.1 87.2
Reprinted in Erwin Schrödinger (2012). “Mind and Matter”, Forward by Roger Penrose: What is Life?: With Mind and Matter and Autobiographical Sketches. Cambridge University Press, p. 118. ISBN 1107604664.
- ↑ ….The World as Will and Representation, vol. I, p. 3
- ↑
Russell Nieli (1987). Wittgenstein: From Mysticism to Ordinary Language; A study of Viennese positivism & the thought of Ludwig Wittgenstein. State University of New York Press. ISBN 0887063985. Quote can be read using Amazon's Look inside feature.
- ↑
Steven Pinker. The Language Instinct: How the mind creates language, Updated reprint of William Morrow and Company 1994. Harper Collins, p. 72. ISBN 0061336467.
- ↑
Steven Pinker. The Language Instinct: How the mind creates language, Updated reprint of William Morrow and Company 1994. Harper Collins, p. 7. ISBN 0061336467.
|