Physical determinism: Difference between revisions
imported>John R. Brews (Russell; some rewording) |
imported>John R. Brews (some clean-up and rewording) |
||
Line 6: | Line 6: | ||
Sometimes the restrictions to ''physical'' events and ''physical'' laws are ignored, and physical determinism is used as a synonym for nomological determinism, that all future events are determined by the past or present. However, in this article this practice is avoided. | Sometimes the restrictions to ''physical'' events and ''physical'' laws are ignored, and physical determinism is used as a synonym for nomological determinism, that all future events are determined by the past or present. However, in this article this practice is avoided. | ||
The initial definition leaves open just what "physical" might mean, or a "complete" description. So, for example, one could | The initial definition leaves open just what "physical" might mean, or a "complete" description. So, for example, one could limit the scope of ''physical determinism'' as | ||
{|align=center style="width:100%;font-size:98%;" | {|align=center style="width:100%;font-size:98%;" | ||
| | | | ||
Line 13: | Line 13: | ||
==Causal completeness== | ==Causal completeness== | ||
The scope of physical determinism is related to the question of the ''causal completeness'' of science, the idea that every event | The scope of physical determinism is related to the question of the ''causal completeness'' of science, the idea that every real event has a scientific explanation, that science need not search for explanations beyond itself.<ref name=Sarkar/>. If causal completeness does not apply to ''everything'' in the universe, then the door is open to events that are not subject to physical determinism.<ref name=Atmanspacher/> For example, a common view of mental events is that they are an [[Epiphenomenalism|epiphenomenon]] only correlated with neurological activity, and without causal impact. However, a failure of physical determinism would allow room for their causal significance. | ||
A more general formulation of physical determinism skirts the issue of causal completeness. It is based upon connections between 'events' supplied by a theory: | A more general formulation of physical determinism skirts the issue of causal completeness. It is based upon connections between 'events' supplied by a theory: | ||
Line 20: | Line 20: | ||
:<font face="Gill Sans MT">"a theory is deterministic if, and only if, given its state variables for some initial period, the theory logically determines a unique set of values for those variables for any other period."<ref name=Nagel/> —Ernest Nagel ''Alternative descriptions of physical state'', p. 292 </font> | :<font face="Gill Sans MT">"a theory is deterministic if, and only if, given its state variables for some initial period, the theory logically determines a unique set of values for those variables for any other period."<ref name=Nagel/> —Ernest Nagel ''Alternative descriptions of physical state'', p. 292 </font> | ||
|} | |} | ||
This quote replaces the idea of 'cause-and-effect' with that of 'logical implication' according to one or another theory that connects events.<ref name=Russell/> In addition, an 'event' is related by the theory itself to formalized ''states'' described using the parameters defined by that theory. Thus, the details of interpretation are placed where they belong, fitted to the context in which the chosen theory applies. Using the definition of physical determinism above, the limitations of a theory to some particular domain of experience also limits the associated definition of 'physical determinism' to that same domain. That limitation leaves open the question whether there is a physical "[[theory of everything]]". | This quote replaces the idea of 'cause-and-effect' with that of 'logical implication' according to one or another theory that connects events.<ref name=Russell/> In addition, an 'event' is related by the theory itself to formalized ''states'' described using the parameters defined by that theory. Thus, the details of interpretation are placed where they belong, fitted to the context in which the chosen theory applies. Using the definition of physical determinism above, the limitations of a theory to some particular domain of experience also limits the associated definition of 'physical determinism' to that same domain. That limitation leaves open the question whether there is a physical "[[theory of everything]]" still to be invented. | ||
==Popper's three worlds== | ==Popper's three worlds== | ||
Line 26: | Line 26: | ||
* World 1: the world of physical [[object (philosophy)|object]]s and [[event (philosophy)|event]]s, including [[biology|biological]] entities | * World 1: the world of physical [[object (philosophy)|object]]s and [[event (philosophy)|event]]s, including [[biology|biological]] entities | ||
* World 2: the world of | * World 2: the mental or psychological world, the world of our feelings of pain and of pleasure, of our thoughts, of our decisions, of our perceptions and our observations; in other words, the world of mental or psychological states or processes, or of subjective experiences. | ||
* World 3: the world of products of the human mind, including art, science, and religion. | * World 3: the world of products of the human mind, including art, science, and religion. | ||
World 3 is a creation of the human imagination | World 3 includes physical theory as a particular case. But World 3 is a creation of the human imagination, and such acts of imagination are a part of World 2. Accordingly, one could argue that physical determinism is a child of the imagination, and although physical determinism has its successes in describing World 1, it may not apply to World 2 or World 3. The subjective aspects of theories contained in World 3 are not readily framed within the third-person perspective of science used to explain World 1. These subjective aspects are described in the article [[Subjective-objective dichotomy]]. | ||
==References== | ==References== | ||
Line 55: | Line 55: | ||
<ref name=Russell> | <ref name=Russell> | ||
The notion of cause introduces unnecessary complications best avoided as done here. For example, see {{cite journal |author=Bertrand Russell |title=On the notion of cause |url=http://www.jstor.org/discover/10.2307/4543833?uid=3739824&uid=2&uid=4&uid=3739256&sid=21101590170351 |journal=Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (New Series) |volume=13 |year=1912-1913 |pages=pp. 1-26}} | The notion of cause introduces unnecessary complications best avoided as done here. For example, see {{cite journal |author=Bertrand Russell |title=On the notion of cause |url=http://www.jstor.org/discover/10.2307/4543833?uid=3739824&uid=2&uid=4&uid=3739256&sid=21101590170351 |journal=Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (New Series) |volume=13 |year=1912-1913 |pages=pp. 1-26}} | ||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Sarkar> | |||
See for example, {{cite book |title=The Philosophy of Science: N-Z, Index |author=Sahotra Sarkar, Jessica Pfeifer |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=b_ixzEzskwYC&pg=PA566 |chapter=Physicalism: The causal impact argument |pages=p. 566 |isbn=041597710X |year=2006 |publisher=Taylor & Francis}} | |||
</ref> | </ref> | ||
}} | }} |
Revision as of 14:45, 26 January 2013
Physical determinism is a position in philosophy that holds that a complete description of the physical state of the world at any given time and a complete statement of the physical laws of nature together entail every truth as to what physical events happen after that time.[1] In different words, physical determinism holds that all physical events occur as described by physical laws.[2]
Sometimes the restrictions to physical events and physical laws are ignored, and physical determinism is used as a synonym for nomological determinism, that all future events are determined by the past or present. However, in this article this practice is avoided.
The initial definition leaves open just what "physical" might mean, or a "complete" description. So, for example, one could limit the scope of physical determinism as
|
Causal completeness
The scope of physical determinism is related to the question of the causal completeness of science, the idea that every real event has a scientific explanation, that science need not search for explanations beyond itself.[3]. If causal completeness does not apply to everything in the universe, then the door is open to events that are not subject to physical determinism.[4] For example, a common view of mental events is that they are an epiphenomenon only correlated with neurological activity, and without causal impact. However, a failure of physical determinism would allow room for their causal significance.
A more general formulation of physical determinism skirts the issue of causal completeness. It is based upon connections between 'events' supplied by a theory:
|
This quote replaces the idea of 'cause-and-effect' with that of 'logical implication' according to one or another theory that connects events.[6] In addition, an 'event' is related by the theory itself to formalized states described using the parameters defined by that theory. Thus, the details of interpretation are placed where they belong, fitted to the context in which the chosen theory applies. Using the definition of physical determinism above, the limitations of a theory to some particular domain of experience also limits the associated definition of 'physical determinism' to that same domain. That limitation leaves open the question whether there is a physical "theory of everything" still to be invented.
Popper's three worlds
A much more general reservation about the applicability of physical determinism stems from the formulation of Popper's three worlds. Popper split the world into three categories:[7]
- World 1: the world of physical objects and events, including biological entities
- World 2: the mental or psychological world, the world of our feelings of pain and of pleasure, of our thoughts, of our decisions, of our perceptions and our observations; in other words, the world of mental or psychological states or processes, or of subjective experiences.
- World 3: the world of products of the human mind, including art, science, and religion.
World 3 includes physical theory as a particular case. But World 3 is a creation of the human imagination, and such acts of imagination are a part of World 2. Accordingly, one could argue that physical determinism is a child of the imagination, and although physical determinism has its successes in describing World 1, it may not apply to World 2 or World 3. The subjective aspects of theories contained in World 3 are not readily framed within the third-person perspective of science used to explain World 1. These subjective aspects are described in the article Subjective-objective dichotomy.
References
- ↑ This definition is from Carl Ginet (1990). On Action. Cambridge University Press, p. 92. ISBN 052138818X.
- ↑ 2.0 2.1 Robert C Bishop (2011). “Chapter 4: Chaos, indeterminism, and free will”, Robert Kane, ed: The Oxford Handbook of Free Will: Second Edition, 2nd. Oxford University Press. ISBN 0195399692.
- ↑ See for example, Sahotra Sarkar, Jessica Pfeifer (2006). “Physicalism: The causal impact argument”, The Philosophy of Science: N-Z, Index. Taylor & Francis, p. 566. ISBN 041597710X.
- ↑ Robert C Bishop, Harald Atmanspacher (2011). “Chapter 5: The causal closure of physics and free will”, Robert Kane, ed: The Oxford Handbook of Free Will: Second Edition, 2nd. Oxford University Press. ISBN 0195399692.
- ↑ Ernest Nagel (1999). “§V: Alternative descriptions of physical state”, The Structure of Science: Problems in the Logic of Scientific Explanation, 2nd. Hackett, pp. 285-292. ISBN 0915144719.
- ↑ The notion of cause introduces unnecessary complications best avoided as done here. For example, see Bertrand Russell (1912-1913). "On the notion of cause". Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (New Series) 13: pp. 1-26.
- ↑ Karl Popper (April 7, 1978). Three Worlds. The Tanner lectures on human values. The University of Utah. Retrieved on 2013-01-24. The list of lectures is found in the Tanner Lecture Library.