Lambda calculus: Difference between revisions

From Citizendium
Jump to navigation Jump to search
imported>Christopher J. Reiss
No edit summary
imported>Christopher J. Reiss
No edit summary
Line 2: Line 2:
In mathematical logic and computer science, the '''lambda calculus''' (also '''λ-calculus''') is a formal system designed to investigate function definition, function application and recursion.  Although it was originally intended as a mathematical formalism and predates the electronic computer, it can be seen as the world's first formalized programming language.  The programming language [[Lisp]] was created in large part from the λ-calculus.  In mathematics, the λ-calculus was central to the first theorems of '''undecidability''' - theorems about the limits of systematic computation which had broad philosophical impact ouside of mathematics.
In mathematical logic and computer science, the '''lambda calculus''' (also '''λ-calculus''') is a formal system designed to investigate function definition, function application and recursion.  Although it was originally intended as a mathematical formalism and predates the electronic computer, it can be seen as the world's first formalized programming language.  The programming language [[Lisp]] was created in large part from the λ-calculus.  In mathematics, the λ-calculus was central to the first theorems of '''undecidability''' - theorems about the limits of systematic computation which had broad philosophical impact ouside of mathematics.


The λ-calculus was introduced by Alonzo Church and Stephen Cole Kleene in the 1930s as part of a larger effort to base the foundation of mathematics upon functions rather than sets (in the hopes of avoiding set-theoretic obstacles like [[Russell's paradox]]). The λ-calculus was ultimately unable to avoid these pitfalls, but emerged as an elegant model of computation.  In 1936 Church used it in his first investigations of Computability, which studies whether certain mathematical problems yield to ''any'' systematic solution by man or machine.    This led to some of the earliest '''undecidability''' results in mathematics which established that certain problems could never be solved by any means.  Perhaps most famously, it was used to give a negative answer to the Halting Problem in the [[Alonzo Church|Church]]-[[Alan Turing|Turing]] Thesis.
The λ-calculus was introduced by Alonzo Church and Stephen Cole Kleene in the 1930s as part of a larger effort to base the foundation of mathematics upon functions rather than sets (in the hopes of avoiding set-theoretic obstacles like [[Russell's paradox]]). The λ-calculus was ultimately unable to avoid these pitfalls, but emerged as a powerful and elegant model of computation.  In 1936 Church used it in his first investigations of Computability, which studies whether certain mathematical problems yield to ''any'' systematic solution by man or machine.    This led to some of the earliest '''undecidability''' results in mathematics which established that certain problems could never be solved by any means.  Perhaps most famously, it was used to give a negative answer to the Halting Problem in the [[Alonzo Church|Church]]-[[Alan Turing|Turing]] Thesis.


The lambda calculus can be thought of as an idealized, minimalist programming language. It is a close cousin of the [[Turing machine]], another  abstraction for modeling computation.  The difference between the two is that the lambda calculus takes a functional view of algorithms, while the original Turing machine takes an imperative view. That is, a Turing machine maintains 'state' - a 'notebook' of symbols that can change from one instruction to the next.  By contrast, the lambda calculus is stateless, it deals exclusively with functions which accept and return data (including other functions), but produce no side effects in 'state' and do not make alterations to incoming data (immutability.)  The functional paradigm can be seen in modern languages like [[Lisp]], [[Scheme]] and [[Haskell]].
The lambda calculus can be thought of as an idealized, minimalist programming language. It is a close cousin of the [[Turing machine]], another  abstraction for modeling computation.  The difference between the two is that the lambda calculus takes a functional view of algorithms, while the original Turing machine takes an imperative view. That is, a Turing machine maintains 'state' - a 'notebook' of symbols that can change from one instruction to the next.  By contrast, the lambda calculus is stateless, it deals exclusively with functions which accept and return data (including other functions), but produce no side effects in 'state' and do not make alterations to incoming data (immutability.)  The functional paradigm can be seen in modern languages like [[Lisp]], [[Scheme]] and [[Haskell]].


The lambda calculus - and the paradigm of functional programming - is still influential, especially within the artificial intelligence community.
The lambda calculus - and the paradigm of functional programming - is still influential, especially within the artificial intelligence community.

Revision as of 16:09, 23 February 2008

This article is a stub and thus not approved.
Main Article
Discussion
Related Articles  [?]
Bibliography  [?]
External Links  [?]
Citable Version  [?]
 
This editable Main Article is under development and subject to a disclaimer.

In mathematical logic and computer science, the lambda calculus (also λ-calculus) is a formal system designed to investigate function definition, function application and recursion. Although it was originally intended as a mathematical formalism and predates the electronic computer, it can be seen as the world's first formalized programming language. The programming language Lisp was created in large part from the λ-calculus. In mathematics, the λ-calculus was central to the first theorems of undecidability - theorems about the limits of systematic computation which had broad philosophical impact ouside of mathematics.

The λ-calculus was introduced by Alonzo Church and Stephen Cole Kleene in the 1930s as part of a larger effort to base the foundation of mathematics upon functions rather than sets (in the hopes of avoiding set-theoretic obstacles like Russell's paradox). The λ-calculus was ultimately unable to avoid these pitfalls, but emerged as a powerful and elegant model of computation. In 1936 Church used it in his first investigations of Computability, which studies whether certain mathematical problems yield to any systematic solution by man or machine. This led to some of the earliest undecidability results in mathematics which established that certain problems could never be solved by any means. Perhaps most famously, it was used to give a negative answer to the Halting Problem in the Church-Turing Thesis.

The lambda calculus can be thought of as an idealized, minimalist programming language. It is a close cousin of the Turing machine, another abstraction for modeling computation. The difference between the two is that the lambda calculus takes a functional view of algorithms, while the original Turing machine takes an imperative view. That is, a Turing machine maintains 'state' - a 'notebook' of symbols that can change from one instruction to the next. By contrast, the lambda calculus is stateless, it deals exclusively with functions which accept and return data (including other functions), but produce no side effects in 'state' and do not make alterations to incoming data (immutability.) The functional paradigm can be seen in modern languages like Lisp, Scheme and Haskell.

The lambda calculus - and the paradigm of functional programming - is still influential, especially within the artificial intelligence community.