Epistemology: Difference between revisions

From Citizendium
Jump to navigation Jump to search
imported>Stephen Ewen
(tweak intro)
mNo edit summary
 
(35 intermediate revisions by 10 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
'''Epistemology''' is the theory of knowingIt studies the phenomenon of knowledge, its nature, and deals with such fundamental questions "What is knowledge?" and "How do we know this?". The term "epistemology" is derived from "ἐπιστήμη" (knowledge) and "λόγος" (logos), and was introduced into English by the Scottish philosopher [[James Frederick Ferrier]]. Epistemology is a branch of [[philosophy]].
{{subpages}}
'''Epistemology''' (from Greek ἐπιστήμη, or ''episteme,'' knowledge; and λόγος, or ''[[logos]]'', a study or account) is also called '''theory of knowledge.''' A [[philosophy|philosophical]] discipline, epistemology deals with broad questions concerning cognition: what is [[knowledge]]? Is [[certainty]] required for knowledge, and what is certainty anyway?  From what sources—[[sense-perception]], say, or [[revelation]]—do we derive knowledge? Our beliefs can have more or less [[justification]], [[warrant]], or [[evidence]]—and these features seem, roughly speaking, required for knowledge. So what are they?  Some thinkers [[doubt]] that we have any, or very much, knowledge at all. On what grounds can we embrace, or reject, such [[skepticism]]?


== Hellenistic views ==
Philosophers have virtually no unanimous views on these topics.  Still, to get the lay of the land, it will help to look at some common opinions.  Many, perhaps most, philosophers hold that knowledge is something like [[JTB analysis|justified, true belief]]; that certainty is not actually required for knowledge; that our basic sources of knowledge include at the very least sense-perception, memory, and reasoning; that our beliefs are justified, ultimately, by a foundation of obvious, self-justifying beliefs, ''or'' by their mutual coherence, ''or'' by being the result of reliable belief-forming processes; and finally, that we are capable of having ''some'' knowledge.  These are just some popular, sample views.  They are very far from being universally held.
Questions involving the nature of knowledge are as old as [[Philosophy]] itself.


[[Plato]] viewed knowledge as universal unchanging Ideas. One dialogue shows how all knowledge is inherent in everyone, whereas another says that that which must be there already to be able to percieve  the world around him.
Occasionally, certain other topics are included in epistemology, particularly the [[philosophy of perception]] as well as questions about [[philosophy of language]], and even [[logic]]. This article, however, is focused on the earlier-listed questions.


[[Aristotle]] tried to divide the types of knowledge, that which can be said of knowledge, into ten Categories. He further attempts to classify knowledge in books named [[physics]], [[metaphysics]], [[poetry]] (including theater), [[biology]] and [[zoology]], [[logic]], [[rhetoric]], [[politics]], [[government]], and [[ethics]]. These areas of knowledge retain his names today.
== The nature of knowledge ==


== Scientific revolution: reason and observation ==
Sometimes we speak as if knowledge is no more than true belief.  But epistemologists (as they are called) are nearly united in their scorn of "true belief" as a definition of knowledge.  Plato famously proposed that knowledge is true belief "with the addition of an account (''logos'')."<ref>Plato, ''Theatetus,'' 201d.  Actually, Plato has Theatetus report something that he remembered: "I had forgotten but now it comes back to me.  He said that true belief with the addition of an account was knowledge, while belief without an account was outside its range."  Later in the dialogue, characteristically, Socrates finds grounds on which to reject this definition.</ref>  An "account" is something like a reason, evidence, or justification, and this seems necessary because of the following sort of situation.  Suppose you're playing [[roulette]], and you're a [[superstition|superstitious]] type of person: you think that, if you believe ''hard enough'' that the ball lands on 7, then the ball will land on 7.  This is, we can stipulate for the example, complete nonsense.  So you believe with all your might that the ball will land on 7, and lo, it lands on 7.  You had a true belief, but not knowledge.  Surely you didn't ''know'', in any strict sense, what number the ball would land on—i.e., your 'true belief' was not 'justified'.  Epistemology studies this ''strict sense'' of knowledge.
The scientific revolution started with questioning old beliefs and the doubt lead to using reason and observation to gain new knowledge, rather than the emphasis of relying on the authority of Plato and Aristotle.


Reason and observation are important for knowledge to all philosophers, but are emphasis as to which was more important started the contention betweeen empiricm and rationalism.
== Justification ==


=== Empiricims ===
Epistemologists are also concerned to understand what it takes for a belief to be [[justification|justified]]. One central question is whether we need to have reasons for thinking our justified beliefs true, and whether we need to be aware of those reasons. [[Coherentism|Coherentists]] answer the first question in the affirmative, and further add that these reasons must be additional justified beliefs which will in turn depend for their justification on other justified beliefs; they are opposed by [[Foundationalism|foundationalists]], who argue that some beliefs can be justified without depending on other beliefs. Some [[accessibilist]] [[Internalism and externalism|internalists]] also answer the second question in the affirmative. But both of these answers are the subject of much dispute.
[[Empiricists]], like [[John Locke]] later stresses the importance of observation and experiments to obtain knowledge, even to the point of assuming that a new born child has a [[tabula rasa]].


=== Rationalism ===
== References ==
[[Rationalists]] like [[René Descartes]] stress reason to arrive at knowledge since one can not always trust the senses.
<references/>


== Modern times ==
== Further Reading ==
[[Immanuel Kant]] tries to resolve many issues, among them the contention between rationalism and empiricism. He uses twelve categories of knowledge and he argues, as Plato did before, that there has to be something in man already there to let observation into the mind. That which is already there before is ''a priori'' and gives a rational basis for handling the empirical knowledge, which is ''a posteriori'' knowledge. Reason corresponds to ''a priori'' and observation to ''a posteriori'' knowledge, thus reconciling rationalism and empiricism.
{{col-begin}}
{{col-break}}
=== Classical works ===
* [[George Berkeley|Berkeley, George]]. ''On the Principles of Human Knowledge''
* [[René Descartes|Descartes, René]]. ''[[Discourse on Method]]''
* [[René Descartes|Descartes, René]]. ''Meditations on First Philosophy''
* [[David Hume|Hume, David]]. ''A Treatise of Human Nature''
* [[Immanuel Kant|Kant, Immanuel]]. ''Critique of Pure Reason''
* [[John Locke|Locke, John]]. ''An Essay Concerning Human Understanding''
* [[Plato]]. ''Meno''
* [[Plato]]. ''Theaetetus''
* [[Sextus Empiricus]]. ''Outlines of Pyrrhonism''
{{col-break}}


== Primary questions and issues ==
=== Contemporary works ===
Epistemology deals largely with
* [[Alfred Jules Ayer|Ayer, A.J.]]. ''The Problem of Knowledge''
 
* [[Laurence BonJour|BonJour, Laurence]]. ''The Structure of Empirical Knowledge''
=== What is knowledge? ===
* [[Laurence BonJour|BonJour, Laurence]]. ''In Defense of Pure Reason''
 
* [[Roderick Chisholm|Chisholm, Roderick]]. ''Theory of Knowledge''
=== How is knowledge proven? ===
* [[Edmund Gettier|Gettier, Edmund]]. Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?"
 
* Alvin Goldman|Goldman, Alvin I. "What is Justified Belief?"
=== How is knowledge acquired? ===
* [[Willard Van Orman Quine|Quine, W. V. O]]. "Epistemology Naturalized"
 
* [[Ludwig Wittgenstein|Wittgenstein, Ludwig]]. ''On Certainty''
== Epistemology outside of philosophy ==
{{col-end}}[[Category:Suggestion Bot Tag]]
Epistemology has found uses in many fields outside of pure philosophy, since the ability to distinguish between knowledge and belief, and to determine what is true and what is false is often useful.
 
*Law: The procedures necessary to establish guilt or innocence or to determine the truth of testimony.
*Science: The ability to distinguish theory from speculation, and what can be established as fact.
*Cognitive science: Dealing with the biology of reasoning, logic, belief, and determining truth.
 
[[category:CZ Live]]
[[category:Philosphy Workgroup]]

Latest revision as of 06:00, 13 August 2024

This article is a stub and thus not approved.
Main Article
Discussion
Related Articles  [?]
Bibliography  [?]
External Links  [?]
Citable Version  [?]
 
This editable Main Article is under development and subject to a disclaimer.

Epistemology (from Greek ἐπιστήμη, or episteme, knowledge; and λόγος, or logos, a study or account) is also called theory of knowledge. A philosophical discipline, epistemology deals with broad questions concerning cognition: what is knowledge? Is certainty required for knowledge, and what is certainty anyway? From what sources—sense-perception, say, or revelation—do we derive knowledge? Our beliefs can have more or less justification, warrant, or evidence—and these features seem, roughly speaking, required for knowledge. So what are they? Some thinkers doubt that we have any, or very much, knowledge at all. On what grounds can we embrace, or reject, such skepticism?

Philosophers have virtually no unanimous views on these topics. Still, to get the lay of the land, it will help to look at some common opinions. Many, perhaps most, philosophers hold that knowledge is something like justified, true belief; that certainty is not actually required for knowledge; that our basic sources of knowledge include at the very least sense-perception, memory, and reasoning; that our beliefs are justified, ultimately, by a foundation of obvious, self-justifying beliefs, or by their mutual coherence, or by being the result of reliable belief-forming processes; and finally, that we are capable of having some knowledge. These are just some popular, sample views. They are very far from being universally held.

Occasionally, certain other topics are included in epistemology, particularly the philosophy of perception as well as questions about philosophy of language, and even logic. This article, however, is focused on the earlier-listed questions.

The nature of knowledge

Sometimes we speak as if knowledge is no more than true belief. But epistemologists (as they are called) are nearly united in their scorn of "true belief" as a definition of knowledge. Plato famously proposed that knowledge is true belief "with the addition of an account (logos)."[1] An "account" is something like a reason, evidence, or justification, and this seems necessary because of the following sort of situation. Suppose you're playing roulette, and you're a superstitious type of person: you think that, if you believe hard enough that the ball lands on 7, then the ball will land on 7. This is, we can stipulate for the example, complete nonsense. So you believe with all your might that the ball will land on 7, and lo, it lands on 7. You had a true belief, but not knowledge. Surely you didn't know, in any strict sense, what number the ball would land on—i.e., your 'true belief' was not 'justified'. Epistemology studies this strict sense of knowledge.

Justification

Epistemologists are also concerned to understand what it takes for a belief to be justified. One central question is whether we need to have reasons for thinking our justified beliefs true, and whether we need to be aware of those reasons. Coherentists answer the first question in the affirmative, and further add that these reasons must be additional justified beliefs which will in turn depend for their justification on other justified beliefs; they are opposed by foundationalists, who argue that some beliefs can be justified without depending on other beliefs. Some accessibilist internalists also answer the second question in the affirmative. But both of these answers are the subject of much dispute.

References

  1. Plato, Theatetus, 201d. Actually, Plato has Theatetus report something that he remembered: "I had forgotten but now it comes back to me. He said that true belief with the addition of an account was knowledge, while belief without an account was outside its range." Later in the dialogue, characteristically, Socrates finds grounds on which to reject this definition.

Further Reading

Classical works

Contemporary works