Free will: Difference between revisions
imported>John R. Brews m (→References: publisher) |
mNo edit summary |
||
(202 intermediate revisions by 2 users not shown) | |||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
{{subpages}} | {{subpages}} | ||
{{TOC|right}} | {{TOC|right}} | ||
'''Free will''' is the | '''Free will''' refers to that feeling, or [https://www.google.com/search?tbo=p&tbm=bks&q=%22experience+of+free+will%22&num=10 experience], one has that one can have complete control to choose among alternative actions, even in the face of psychological and other conflicting influences.<ref name=Lamont/><ref name=GStrawson/><ref name=Gallagher0/><ref name=Holton/> As a phenomenon, 'free will' transcends any encapsulation in words, just like an eclipse of the moon is a phenomenon that can be addressed by devouring dragons or by planetary motions, but still is an eclipse, however it is described. A difference from an eclipse, however, is that the experience of free will, despite its prevalence, is not established objectively by third-party observations, but by introspection and by reports by others of their own subjective mental life. Whether we all are deluded, or whether the matter lies outside or within the reach of science, the experience is there, and these and other wide-ranging questions about this experience are part of its exploration.<ref name=Britannica/> | ||
It is an age-old concern to separate what we can do something about, choose to do, from what we cannot. Much of human experience is interpreted as depending upon our choices. Capturing the content of this subjective formulation, one stance regarding '''free will''' is the philosophical position that human beings are able to choose between different courses of action in any given circumstance,<ref name=free/> whereas the opposite position, '''[[determinism]]''', claims that all our mental states and actions are made necessary by preceding causes, and the idea that we are free at all is an illusion.<ref name=Cornman/> | |||
These diametric extremes, on the one hand we always are in complete control, and on the other that we never are in control, unnecessarily restrict our options, an example of ''[[false dichotomy]],''<ref name=dichotomy/> referred to specifically in this instance as ''naïve dualism''.<ref name=Monterosso/> Reality lies somewhere else, as it is abundantly clear that our actions can be dictated by factors outside our control and outside our awareness,<ref name=Harris/> but it is unclear that such factors are decisive in every instance or in the long run. The present situation is that the ability to exercise free will is known definitely to be limited by many factors, sometimes strongly limited. An alternative to the "either-or" formulation is [[#Libertarianism|metaphysical libertarianism]], which simply asserts that ''determinism'' is false, and at least sometimes humans exert control over their choices.<ref name=Balaguer/> However, a useful discussion of free will may require vocabulary and concepts not yet developed, and whatever its ultimate formulation, a persuasive account of ''free will'' requires an extrapolation of the present understanding of the brain and the mind beyond what is verifiable today.<ref name=NagelT/><ref name=NagelT2/> | |||
The controllable and uncontrollable aspects of decision making are logically separable using the following device: | The controllable and uncontrollable aspects of decision making are logically separable using the following device: | ||
{|align=left style="width:90%;font-size:97%;" | |||
| | |||
:<font face="Gill Sans MT">"Philosophers who distinguish ''freedom of action'' and ''freedom of will'' do so because our success in carrying out our ends depends in part on factors wholly beyond our control. Furthermore, there are always external constraints on the range of options we can meaningfully try to undertake. As the presence or absence of these conditions and constraints are not (usually) our responsibility, it is plausible that the central loci of our responsibility are our choices, or “willings.”</font> Timothy O'Connor, ''Free Will'' <ref name=OConnor/>[Italics not in original.] | |||
|} | |||
{|align=center style="width:100%;font-size:100%;" | |||
| | |||
The connection between ''will'' and ''action'' thereby is separated for further discussion. In particular, is there in nature anything that actually inhabits the domain of "will" so-defined, a domain beyond the reach of "external constraints"? A related distinction is that between [[Brain#Mind_and_brain|''brain'' and ''mind'']], with ''brain'' the physical matter where mental processes take place, and ''mind'' somehow (unclearly) related to consciousness and will. | |||
|} | |||
All of us have subjectively experienced being torn between doing one thing or another –what we would ''like'' to do, what we think we ''should'' do, or what we think others would appreciate our doing, and so on. We might assume that the decision is up to us, that we are free to do one thing or another, and others may heap blame or praise on us assuming the same thing. This assumption is what is meant by ''free will'' –the intuition that whatever we may have done in actual fact, could have been otherwise because we might have decided on another course of action, and that before taking the action we were free to choose between alternatives. The claim might be: "Consciousness has the ability to override its genetic (and other) instructions and to set its own independent course of action."<ref name=Csikszentmihalyi/> | |||
At the same time, we realize that some aspects of the world work in ways that can be understood because there are law-like processes that can be deciphered, and that allow us to predict some future events based upon observations of past events. The principle operating here is that future events are governed by physical laws rooted in past events, and the notion that this kind of explanation applies to everything that happens is known as [[determinism]]. Some have argued that the probabilistic nature of [[quantum mechanics]] opens a door to a randomness in human behavior, which is foreign to human experience. Inasmuch as random atomic events are not under our control any more than predetermined events, determinism can be rewritten to include this randomness, for example, as follows: All our decisions are either implied by past events, or by random events, that in both cases do not involve us as agents, but which we simply witness.<ref name=Balaguer/> | |||
If the world is deterministic, our feeling that we are free to choose an action is simply an illusion. We have trouble believing all our actions are beyond our control, and that our sense of freedom is totally illusory, but we also have problems thinking that our actions are totally within our control. Although it is an exaggeration (at least at the moment) to think that science requires determinism,<ref name=determinism/> it is apparent that "consciousness plays a far smaller role in human life than Western culture has tended to believe."<ref name=illusion/><ref name=Eagleman/> | |||
This dilemma is what in philosophy is known as the ''problem of free will'' (or sometimes referred to by its flip-side as the [[dilemma of determinism]]), and it is a dilemma because it is difficult to decide how to assign [[moral responsibility]] for our actions. In a more nuanced formulation, the dilemma stems from the question posed as follows: | |||
{|align="center" style="width:90%;font-size:97%;" | |||
| | |||
<font face="Gill Sans MT">"Are behaviors, judgments, and other higher mental processes the product of free conscious choices, as influenced by internal psychological states (motives, preferences, ''etc.''), or are those higher mental processes determined by those states?" </font> John A. Bargh, ''Free Will is Un-natural''<ref name=Bargh/> | |||
|} | |||
A clear statement of the dilemma is as follows: | |||
{|align="center" style="width:90%;font-size:97%;" | {|align="center" style="width:90%;font-size:97%;" | ||
| | | | ||
<font face="Gill Sans MT">" | <font face="Gill Sans MT">"The idea of free will, though now rather in disfavor, expressed the popular and philosophical view that behavior reflects the outcome of a struggle between an autonomous, relatively virtuous, possibly spiritual self and the baser forces of external demand and inner cravings. The assumption that two different processes battle it out to determine action has been fundamental in theological views, such as beliefs about the judgment of individual souls based upon whether they choose virtuous or sinful acts. Likewise, it is central to some modern legal judgments that assign punishment not just on the basis of the action and its (criminal) consequences but also on the supposed state of mind of the perpetrator – reserving lesser punishment for crimes committed in mental states...that supposedly reduce the capacity of the nobler part of the self to restrain the wickeder impulses..." </font> Roy F Baumeister ''et al.'', ''Free Willpower: A limited resource theory of volition, choice and self-regulation''<ref name=Baumeister/> | ||
|} | |} | ||
== Mind-body problem== | |||
{{main|Mind-body problem}} | |||
{{Image|Some brain areas.png|right|350px|Some human brain areas involved in mental disorders. Area 25 refers to [http://spot.colorado.edu/~dubin/talks/brodmann/brodmann.html Brodmann's area 25], a region implicated in long-term depression.<ref name=LTD/>}} | |||
The idea of free will is one aspect of the [[mind-body problem]], that is, consideration of the relation between mind (for example, consciousness, memory and judgment) and body (for example, the human brain and nervous system). The 'mind' may not be coterminous with the brain, as Schrödinger has suggested,<ref name=Schrodinger/> and [[cultural psychology]] suggests that "Culture produces the mind; brain circuitry does not."<ref name=Ratner/> [[Extended cognition|Enactivists]] take the view that the brain, the mind, the environment, form a tightly coupled system that, at least in some aspects, defies separation into individual quasi-autonomous pieces.<ref name=Hutto/> | |||
In the context of free will, does the relation between mind and body allow for the mind to 'cause' neurological states, or is the mind simply an artifact or correlate of what the brain and nervous system are doing on their own? That question is presented as though the issue is empirical, but there are serious questions as to whether it is properly phrased that way, and whether standard methods separating the ''observed'' from the ''observer'' really apply to this investigation. Are there causal connections behind known correlations between subjective mental activity and objectively identified neurological events? Is the language of 'cause' and 'effect' too limited to describe huge systems of sensors with complex feedback arrangements? The discussion of free will falls into various parts: some empirical (What is going on in the brain?), some semantic (What are the possible meanings of free will, and are new concepts necessary?), some theoretical (there are many of these, among them: Does the disturbance of what is observed by the very act of observation imply that terms like ''free will'' and the terms used in neuroscience are fundamentally incompatible descriptions, making psychology irreducible to neuroscience?). | |||
For example, ''interactionalist dualism'' suggests that some physical events cause some mental acts and some mental acts cause some physical events. Dualism allows humans free will, because mind only is ''correlated'' with brain activity, and is not reducible to it.<ref name=Peruzzi/> A modern dualist position from the field of [[artificial intelligence]], or ''AI'', is made by so called ''strong AI'' theorists, who say that the mind is separate from the brain in the same way that a computer algorithm exists independent of its many possible realizations in coding and physical implementation, and the brain and its 'wiring' is analogous to a [[computer]] and its [[software]].<ref name=AI/> (Perhaps it is worth pointing out that the brain and its operation is known to be quite different from any man-made computer.<ref name=computer/>) Another version is the "three world" formulation of [[Karl Popper|Popper]].<ref name=Popper/> These are examples of what is called ''epistemological pluralism'', that is the notion that the mind-body problem is not reducible to the concepts of the natural sciences. | |||
One contrasting approach is called ''cognitive naturalism'', in which mind is simply part of nature, perhaps merely a feature of most very complex self-programming feedback systems, and must be studied by the methods of empirical science.<ref name=Peruzzi/> Certainly, some areas of the brain (see image) are connected to aspects of mental function and consciousness. | |||
== | Attempts are being made to soften the boundary between these two views based upon [[self-organizing system]]s, exploring the conjecture that such systems can have a causal power over the organization of their deterministic subsystems, expressed in the ways these substratum elements are organized and put into action.<ref name=Ellis/> | ||
{|align="center" style="width:90%;font-size:97%;" | |||
| | |||
<font face="Gill Sans MT">“What must be explained is how a self-organizing or dynamical system can have a causal power over its own substrata, which is not reducible to the sum of the actions of the substrata, while at the same time causal closure is not violated at the substratum level.[...] any such causal analysis must use a theory of self-organization as their starting point, since only a dynamical system promises [...] the power to appropriate substratum elements into its own basins of attraction, rather than letting those basins be merely a higher-level description of the independent actions of the substrata.”</font> R. D. Ellis ''Part III. The mind-body problem''<ref name=Ellis/>, p.49. | |||
|} | |||
One aspect of this development is to explore the question: Is a machine realizable for which the goals of the machine are not imposed from the outside, but produced by the machine itself?<ref name=Atlan/> | |||
An outstanding unsolved issue in the mind-body problem often is called the [[hard problem of consciousness]], how physical phenomena acquire subjective characteristics becoming, for example, colors and tastes.<ref name=Kalat/> For example, "it is possible to know all the physical and functional facts concerning the operation of human brains without, for example, knowing what it is like subjectively to experience [[vertigo]]."<ref name=Loewer/> The subjective intuition of free will may fall into this category as well. | |||
== | ==Philosophical positions== | ||
The discussion of ''free will'' sprang historically from attempts to reconcile the sense that the mind could freely make decisions that affected a person's future with the observation that at least some things in nature were simply the consequences of other things. A more modern view of ''free will'' concerns the relation between the subjective, ''free will'', ''color'', ''taste'', and the objective or scientific mode of observation. Both are outlined below. | |||
Others have argued that determinism is ''false'', or that at the very least, human actions are a special case and stand outside the requirements of a deterministic universe.<ref name=Balaguer/> In simple terms, freedom of thought is distinguished from freedom of action, and their connection is made a subject of study. By separating the rules of thought, one might be free to choose between alternatives, one might have ''causal powers''. | ===Compatibilist-incompatibilist arguments=== | ||
Using ''T'', ''F'' for "true" and "false" and ''?'' for undecided, there are exactly nine positions regarding ''determinism/free will'' that consist of any two of these three possibilities:<ref name=Strawson/> | |||
{| class="wikitable" style="text-align:center; width:50%;" | |||
|+Galen Strawson's table <ref name=Strawson/> | |||
|- | |||
| | |||
! scope="col" | 1 | |||
! scope="col" | 2 | |||
! scope="col" | 3 | |||
! scope="col" | 4 | |||
! scope="col" | 5 | |||
! scope="col" | 6 | |||
! scope="col" | 7 | |||
! scope="col" | 8 | |||
! scope="col" | 9 | |||
|- | |||
!scope="row"| Determinism ''D'' | |||
|T | |||
|F | |||
|T | |||
|F | |||
|T | |||
|F | |||
|? | |||
|? | |||
|? | |||
|- | |||
!scope="row"| Free will ''FW'' | |||
|F | |||
|T | |||
|T | |||
|F | |||
|? | |||
|? | |||
|F | |||
|T | |||
|? | |||
|- | |||
|} | |||
''Incompatibilism'' may occupy any of the nine positions except (5), (8) or (3), which last corresponds to ''soft determinism''. Position (1) is ''hard determinism'',and position (2) is ''libertarianism''. The position (1) of hard determinism adds to the table the contention that ''D'' implies ''FW'' is untrue, and the position (2) of libertarianism adds the contention that ''FW'' implies ''D'' is untrue. Position (9) may be called ''hard incompatibilism'' if one interprets ''?'' as meaning both concepts are of dubious value. ''Compatibilism'' itself may occupy any of the nine positions, that is, there is no logical contradiction between determinism and free will, and either or both may be true or false in principle. Below some of these positions are examined in more detail.<ref name=Strawson/><ref name=Strawson2/> | |||
==== Incompatibilism ==== | |||
{|align="center" style="width:90%;font-size:97%;" | |||
| | |||
<font face="Gill Sans MT">“Experience teaches us no less clearly than reason, that men believe themselves to be free, simply because they are conscious of their actions, and unconscious of the causes whereby those actions are determined.”</font> B de Spinoza ''Ethics''<ref name=Spinoza/> | |||
|} | |||
One approach, of course, is simply to accept as a fact that human beings are not free, a position termed ''hard'' determinism or ''incompatibilism''.<ref name=Balaguer/> To accept this position is to accept that our actions are caused by things other than our ''will'' –that actions do not originate in ''volition'' (willing), but rather in forces that determine its disposition in one way or another, a view often associated with [[stoicism]].<ref name=stoic/> Hard determinism, however, insofar as it accepts a causal chain of events, means our present actions are determined in the past, and some consider that view to wholly destroy any notion of moral responsibility. From this stance, freedom is considered a necessary component of responsibility, for why should anyone be blamed or praised for actions that could not have been otherwise? | |||
[[Stoicism|Stoics]], however, considered that an agent was responsible for thinking through their choices, even though the appearance of choice is illusory.<ref name=stoic/> This curious situation led to much debate over the centuries, with [[Chrysippus]] (279 – 206 BC) attempting a way out of this apparent contradiction by separating external ''antecedent'' causes from the internal disposition receiving this cause, similar temptations affect those of different character differently, a solution adopted by many thinkers since that time in various formulations.<ref name=Chrysippus/> | |||
Classically, the idea of determinism goes back at least as far as [[Pierre Simon Laplace|Laplace]], who posited (based upon [[Isaac Newton|Newton]]'s laws of mechanics) that an omniscient observer knowing with infinite precision all the positions and velocities of every particle in the universe could predict the future entirely. Needless to say, omniscient observers are imaginary creations.<ref name=Higgins/> A less restrictive view of determinism than that of Laplace is discussed by Nagel.<ref name=Nagel/> "A theory is deterministic if, and only if, given its state variables for some initial period, the theory logically determines a unique set of values for those variables for any other period." To extend this idea to a view of determinism, in addition one would have to assert that the Universe is governed, at least in principle, by some amalgam of deterministic theories. Nagel argues that a deterministic formulation does not require the viability of omniscient observers, but only the possibility in principle of determinism: "A theory is labeled properly as a deterministic one if analysis of its internal structure shows that the theoretical state of a system at one instant logically determines a unique state of that system for another instant." The use of the term "state" incorporates [[Field theory (physics)|field theories]] like the [[Standard Model]] within determinism. | |||
==== Libertarianism ==== | |||
Others have argued that determinism is ''false'', or that at the very least, human actions are a special case and stand outside the requirements of a deterministic universe.<ref name=Balaguer/> In simple terms, freedom of thought is distinguished from freedom of action, and their connection is made a subject of study. By separating the rules of thought, one might be free to choose between alternatives, one might have ''causal powers''. | |||
[[Augustine of Hippo|Saint Augustine]] held this view, the capacity for ''metaphysical freedom''.<ref name=Augustine/> [[Immanuel Kant|Kant]] also subscribed to this view: besides ''nature'' and empirical knowledge, there is the realm of ''things in themselves'' accessible to thought and governed by different rules; a distinction between ''phenomena'' and ''noumena''.<ref name=Kant/> | [[Augustine of Hippo|Saint Augustine]] held this view, the capacity for ''metaphysical freedom''.<ref name=Augustine/> [[Immanuel Kant|Kant]] also subscribed to this view: besides ''nature'' and empirical knowledge, there is the realm of ''things in themselves'' accessible to thought and governed by different rules; a distinction between ''phenomena'' and ''noumena''.<ref name=Kant/> | ||
There are other ways to suggest that "reality" is larger than the realm where determinism applies. For example, [[Pierre Duhem]] suggested that scientific theory was simply a device to facilitate economy of thought, and could not be considered to encompass "reality".<ref name=Duhem/> Thus, thought is a distillation of reality, and what goes on "in reality" is a much deeper and broader question than how we describe it. Similar to consciousness itself, scientific theory is a synopsis of some of what goes on, not the full text. This view of science as dealing with only part of the picture opens the way to more modern statements of the separation of causality in nature from that in the mind. | |||
== Compatibilism == | Another way to limit the applicability of determinism is to introduce the role of subjectivity, more generally, consciousness, as a matter beyond the reach of the methods of science and its requirement for public verifiability. So, for example, [[pain]] is a subjective phenomenon. It can sometimes be correlated to verifiable events in the nervous system, but the experience of pain is inaccessible except through subjective reports from the victim. The so-far unobtainable goal of relating subjective experiences like pain, color, taste to verifiable constructs is called the [[hard problem of consciousness]],<ref name= Goldstein0/> and the experience of ''free will'' falls under this label. An additional issue related to this separation of the subjective and the objective is the question of [[mental causation]],<ref name=Harbecke/> the ability (or not) of the mind to affect the material world. This concern may have more respectable goals than establishing [[Psychokinesis|telekinesis]]. | ||
For example, we have this modern statement of the claim for mental causation: | |||
{|align="center" style="width:90%;font-size:97%;" | |||
| | |||
<font face="Gill Sans MT">"The nonconcious forms of self-regulation may follow different causal principles and do not rely on the same resources as the conscious and effortful ones." </font> Roy F Baumeister ''et al.'', ''Free Willpower: A limited resource theory of volition, choice and self-regulation''<ref name=Baumeister/> | |||
|} | |||
A different approach questions the concept of "causality" itself, considering it a construct inappropriate to the description of human and animal behavior. See the section below on [[#Causality|causality]]. | |||
==== Compatibilism ==== | |||
An intermediate view has been to soften the requirements of what it means to be free. One accepts the fact that actions have causes, but argues that this does not mean we are not free.<ref name=Balaguer/> | An intermediate view has been to soften the requirements of what it means to be free. One accepts the fact that actions have causes, but argues that this does not mean we are not free.<ref name=Balaguer/> | ||
In the approach known as ''soft determinism'', I am still free even though my character, common sense and so forth, strongly support a course of action, because they do not ''compel'' me to act in this way, nor preclude alternatives. Of course freedom understood in this way is not an arbitrary freedom. It is freedom in the sense that nothing stops me from doing otherwise, even though it is unlikely. Put in an extreme form: "A puppet is free as long as he loves his strings".<ref name= | In the approach known as ''soft determinism'', I am still free even though my character, common sense and so forth, strongly support a course of action, because they do not ''compel'' me to act in this way, nor preclude alternatives. Of course freedom understood in this way is not an arbitrary freedom. It is freedom in the sense that nothing stops me from doing otherwise, even though it is unlikely. Put in an extreme form: "A puppet is free as long as he loves his strings".<ref name=Harris2/> | ||
What are the "strings" attached to our decisions? The questions of character, predisposition, programming and so on, are part of the field of [[behaviorism]], where behavior modification, reinforcement, and so forth are studied.<ref name=Skinner/> A closely related field is [[cognitive psychology]], the [[psychology]] of [[cognition]], studying matters such as the processes involved in memorization and decision making.<ref name=Goldstein/><ref name=Sternberg/> | What are the "strings" attached to our decisions? The questions of character, predisposition, programming and so on, are part of the field of [[behaviorism]], where behavior modification, reinforcement, and so forth are studied.<ref name=Skinner/> A closely related field is [[cognitive psychology]], the [[psychology]] of [[cognition]], studying matters such as the processes involved in memorization and decision making.<ref name=Goldstein/><ref name=Sternberg/> | ||
===Subjective-objective dichotomy=== | |||
{{main|Subjective-objective dichotomy}} | |||
An undecided question is whether the world of science and the universe are coextensive. Science has practical impact upon technology and our understanding of interconnections. However, there are areas where science so far has had little impact. So there exists a difference in optimism about science, with one view opining that science will gradually extend to everything, and the opposite view opining that won't happen. For example, the statement is found in many books: | |||
{|align="center" style="width:90%;font-size:97%;" | |||
|<font face="Gill Sans MT">"...consciousness is a biological process that will eventually be explained in terms of molecular signaling pathways used by interacting populations of nerve cells.."</font> –Eric R. Kandel, ''In Search of Memory: The Emergence of a New Science of Mind - ''<ref name=Kandel/> | |||
|} | |||
On the other hand, the contrary view is described below in the section on [[#Complementarity|complementarity]].<ref name=Northoff/><ref name=analogy/> | |||
''Free will'' is an arena in which to contrast these viewpoints. ''Free will'' is a widely shared intuition.<ref name=Caruso/> Like other aspects of consciousness, it appears to escape inclusion in a scientific explanation, and one has to ask whether science can say anything useful about this intuition. ''Free will'' stands at the nexus between subjective and objective realities, and is possibly the most interesting situation where these two meet. | |||
Free will often is contrasted with determinism. In considering a statement involving determinism, like ''All events ''p'' are determined by other events ''P'' '', in order to be consistent with science today, and avoid oversimplification, one has to be very clear about how the events (p,P) are defined. One also has to replace "determined" by something like "logically imply". | |||
{|align="center" style="width:90%;font-size:97%;" | |||
|<font face="Gill Sans MT"> "a theory is deterministic if, and only if, given its state variables for some initial period, the theory logically determines a unique set of values for those variables for any other period."</font> –Ernest Nagel, ''Alternative descriptions of physical state'' <ref name=Nagel0/> | |||
|} | |||
The need for great care in defining "events" and "determined" results in detailed descriptions of what constitutes an "event" and how one is said to "determine" another, and raises questions of how to relate the "universe" to these detailed descriptions. | |||
These developments take the subjective-objective distinction to a more general level than simply arguments over the prospects of success of extending science into certain areas of experience. A [[Karl Popper|Popper]]-like view emerges with an "event" as some kind of formalized "state" and the relationship "determines" phrased as a "logical implication" of connection between states, all combined as parts of one or another abstract theory. That formalization puts a lot of emphasis upon mental constructions. From the stance of a [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/duhem/ Duhem], or a [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/popper/ Popper], or a [[Model-dependent realism|Hawking]], the use of an intermediary, elaborate mental construction is a meld of the subjective and objective. It is used to determine connections about objective events, but the form of the theoretical construct is a product of subjective activities, and its particular form may well be more about the brain than anything else. Much like a computer [[algorithm]] can be expressed as [[assembly language]] instructions peculiar to a particular computer by translating the algorithm into steps that particular computer can handle, some aspects of the universe's operation can be expressed in terms of mental constructs. | |||
Lest this apparatus be thought of as an entirely formal understanding, some among us actually do have intuitive grasp of these abstractions, perhaps analogous to the fact that some among us hear music in the sounds around them. Quoting Feynman about his creative process: | |||
{|align="center" style="width:90%;font-size:97%;" | |||
|<font face="Gill Sans MT">"It is impossible to differentiate the symbols from the thing; but it is very visual. It is hard to believe it, but I see these things not as mathematical expressions but a mixture of a mathematical expression wrapped into and around, in a vague way, around the object. So I see all the time visual things associated with what I am trying to do."</font> –Richard P. Feyman, as quoted by Schweber: ''QED and the men who made it: Dyson, Feynman, Schwinger, and Tomonaga''<ref name=Schweber/> | |||
|} | |||
This comment could be paralleled by others about the intuitions of musicians and mathematicians.<ref name=Copland/> The point is that the creation of scientific theories is subjective, and the very concepts of determinism are themselves subjective and mutable creations of the human mind. What is in charge here: the intuition conceiving the theory, or the theory that results; or is it an unending back-and-forth spiral from one to the other? Using such theory to assess mental activity itself, including free will, is something of a [[bootstrap]]ping process that might never converge. The question of whether an intuitive ''free will'' submits to a critique by some deterministic theory has aspects of an [[infinite regress]]. Did a rat "decide" to run a maze, or was it "instinct"? Did the biologist in the laboratory "decide" to build the maze, or was it the [http://www.oxforddictionaries.com/us/definition/american_english/zeitgeist ''zeitgeist''] of the field? Did the corporation "decide" to build the laboratory, or was it a fad?<ref name=Shapiro/> | |||
{|align="center" style="width:90%;font-size:97%;" | |||
|<font face="Gill Sans MT">"When stated at a general level, the subjective/objective dichotomy is recognized by most social scientists as one of the enduring metatheoretical dilemmas in the social sciences..."</font> –David Swartz: ''Culture and Power: The Sociology of Pierre Bourdieu'', p. 55<ref name=Swartz/> | |||
|} | |||
{|align="center" style="width:90%;font-size:97%;" | |||
|<font face="Gill Sans MT">"It is not possible to resolve which of the subjective or physical universes ultimately contains the other."</font> –Alec Rogers: ''Cognitive Set Theory'', p.85<ref name=Rogers/> | |||
|} | |||
==Complementarity== | ==Complementarity== | ||
Line 52: | Line 185: | ||
{|align="center" style="width:90%;font-size:97%;" | {|align="center" style="width:90%;font-size:97%;" | ||
| | | | ||
<font face="Gill Sans MT">"...it is important to be clear about exactly what experience one wants one's subjects to introspect. Of course, explaining to subjects exactly what the experimenter wants them to experience can bring its own problems–...instructions to attend to a particular internally generated experience can easily alter both the timing and he content of that experience and even whether or not it is consciously experienced at all." </font>Susan Pockett, ''The neuroscience of movement''<ref name=Pockett/> | <font face="Gill Sans MT">"...it is important to be clear about exactly what experience one wants one's subjects to introspect. Of course, explaining to subjects exactly what the experimenter wants them to experience can bring its own problems–...instructions to attend to a particular internally generated experience can easily alter both the timing and he content of that experience and even whether or not it is consciously experienced at all." </font> Susan Pockett, ''The neuroscience of movement''<ref name=Pockett/> | ||
|} | |||
Another description of this issue is by Northoff:<ref name=Northoff/> | |||
{|align="center" style="width:90%;font-size:97%;" | |||
| | |||
<font face="Gill Sans MT">"Epistemically, the mind is determined by mental states, which are accessible in First-Person Perspective. In contrast, the brain, as characterized by neuronal states, can be accessed in Third-Person Perspective. The Third-Person Perspective focuses on other persons and thus on the neuronal states of others' brain while excluding the own brain. In contrast, the First-Person Perspective could potentially provide epistemic access to own brain...However, the First-Person Perspective provides access only to the own mental states but not to the own brain and its neuronal states."</font> Georg Northoff, ''Philosophy of the Brain: The Brain Problem'', p. 5<ref name=Northoff/> | |||
|} | |||
These observations suggest the possibility that "free will" and neurology inhabit different realms, and it is confusion to try to explain "free will" using a neurological approach that by its very nature excludes the effects of observation upon what is observed. In broad terms, this argument complements that of Chrysippus (279 – 206 BC).<ref name=Chrysippus/> | |||
==Causality== | |||
In extending the application of the principle of complementarity, Bohr questioned the everyday ideas of causality: | |||
{|align="center" style="width:70%;font-size:97%;" | |||
| | |||
<font face="Gill Sans MT">"...any observation necessitates an interference with the course of the phenomena, which is of such a nature that it deprives us of the foundation underlying the causal mode of description."</font> Neils Bohr: ''The Atomic Theory and the Fundamental Principles underlying the Description of Nature''<ref name=Bohr/> | |||
|} | |||
Bohr considered these reservations might apply in trying to explain the connection between mental and physical events in terms of observation altering what is observed. If our notion of causality is questioned, "free will" as mental causation takes on a different interpretation. | |||
Similar reservations have been expressed by others, but take a broader, more historical approach. Historically, two types of causality (the "being responsible for something else") are distinguished, with several sub-genres.<ref name=ElBizri/> The first kind of causes is that which is included in the effect and is part of it (embedment); the arising of something out of itself. The second kind of causes does not reside in the effect and is separate from it. | |||
In the first category, two subdivisions arise: | |||
:''causa materialis'' or material cause: the implied but not yet realized result, as Michelangelo said his act of sculpture "released" the form already present and buried within the marble.<ref name=Michelangelo/> | |||
:''causa formalis'' or formal causality: a mental construct created to relate an effect to a cause. | |||
The second category of external causes also divides into two: | |||
:''causa efficiencs'' or efficient causality: cause and effect can be separated and determined, the usual 'cause' of science as stimulus and response. | |||
:''causa finalis'' or final causality: the objective as shaping the action; as may entail its expression though no cause as yet exists. Thus, the desire for a king may cause a coronation, and goals set by evolution may determine a response. | |||
These notions of cause may not be all that distinct. For example, the "principle of least action", and its extension to the [[Feynman path integral]], predicts the realized path of a system as a minimization of 'action' over all possible paths, seemingly suggesting that the system 'action' (a ''causa materialis'') already embodies the path to be taken given the objective of 'least action' (a ''causa finalis''). And yet this formulation is equivalent to those based upon Newton's laws or quantum mechanics, which invoke only ''causa efficiencs'', and it has been argued that physics theories themselves constitute a ''causa formalis'', no more than a mental shorthand to link selected events, a subset of all events.<ref name=Duhem/> | |||
Northoff regards the restriction of cause to ''causa efficiencs'' precludes a proper understanding of the dynamics and self-organization of the brain, restricting explanations to an 'outside of the brain' point of view: “the possibility of mental causation is necessarily dependent on the possibility of 'final and formal causality'”.<ref name=Northoff2/> | |||
Along these lines, Freeman introduces the replacement of "causality" by what he calls "circular causality" to "allow for the contribution of self-organizing dynamics", the "formation of macroscopic population dynamics that shapes the patterns of activity of the contributing individuals", applicable to "interactions between neurons and neural masses...and between the behaving animal and its environment": | |||
{|align="center" style="width:90%;font-size:97%;" | |||
| | |||
<font face="Gill Sans MT">"Circular causality departs so strongly from the classical tenets of necessity, invariance, and precise temporal order that the only reason to call it that is to satisfy the human habitual need for causes....The very strong appeal of agency to explain events may come from the subjective experience of cause and effect that develops early in human life, before the acquisition of language...the question I raise here is whether brains share this property with other material objects in the world. " </font> (Walter J. Freeman, ''Consciousness, intentionality and causality''<ref name=Freeman/>) | |||
|} | |||
Freeman's usage for the term ''circular causality'' appears akin to the views of Kelso,<ref name=Kelso/> and is more radical than the common use of this term, which refers to causality in a system with [[feedback]].<ref name=feedback/> A more specific use of this term is as follows: | |||
{|align="center" style="width:90%;font-size:97%;" | |||
| | |||
<font face="Gill Sans MT">"Note we are dealing here with circular causality. On the one hand the [[order parameter]] enslaves the atoms, but on the other hand it is itself generated by the joint action of the atoms" </font> (Hermann Haken, ''Information and Self-Organization: A Macroscopic Approach to Complex Systems''<ref name=Haken/>) | |||
|} | |} | ||
==Self-programming robots== | ==Self-programming robots== | ||
{{See also|Robot|Robotics}} | {{See also|Robot|Robotics}} | ||
Today robots can be made that adapt their responses to their environment through self-programming, so-called intelligent robots. Much of the description of these machines seems parallel to human behavior, although technology has still not reached sufficient complexity to make a strong case for the | Today robots can be made that adapt their responses to their environment through self-programming, so-called intelligent robots. Much of the description of these machines seems parallel to human behavior, although technology has still not reached sufficient complexity to make a strong case for the similarities.<ref name=Zelazo/> | ||
{|align="center" style="width:90%;font-size:97%;" | {|align="center" style="width:90%;font-size:97%;" | ||
|- | |- | ||
|<font face="Gill Sans MT">"Some people think that consciousness can arise only in organic, of flesh-and-blood beings. Others speculate that self-awareness might develop in any sufficiently complex network that is set up to operate like a brain...Could a conscious robot – a being created by humans and not by God – ever be said to have a soul? "</font><ref name=Stefoff/> | |<font face="Gill Sans MT">"Some people think that consciousness can arise only in organic, of flesh-and-blood beings. Others speculate that self-awareness might develop in any sufficiently complex network that is set up to operate like a brain...Could a conscious robot – a being created by humans and not by God – ever be said to have a soul? "</font><ref name=Stefoff/> | ||
|} | |} | ||
Is such a machine deterministic? We cannot predict the machine's exact behavior without a complete knowledge of its personal history with its environment, the reliability of its components, and its present state of programming, uncertainties in which limit us to probabilistic statements. | Is such a machine deterministic? We cannot predict the machine's exact behavior without a complete knowledge of its personal history with its environment, the reliability of its components, and its present state of programming, uncertainties in which limit us to probabilistic statements. It may be that this question is objectively undecidable, and has only an answer according to some or another theoretical formulation, in particular, a statistical answer indicating a probable range of responses to a probable range of inputs. | ||
Groups of cooperating robots also are envisioned: | Groups of cooperating robots also are envisioned: | ||
Line 75: | Line 252: | ||
|} | |} | ||
==Addiction== | ==Implementation of decisions== | ||
[[Decision theory]] describes the processes, constraints, and determinants of human decision making.<ref name= Kozielecki/><ref name=Chater/> In connection with free will, an important aspect of these studies is autonomy, the ability of individuals "to determine the direction of their lives in accordance with their beliefs, principles and values".<ref name=Mackenzie/> Brain studies have provided some insight into the brain functions involved in decisions and their implementation. | |||
===Addiction=== | |||
{{Main|Addiction}} | {{Main|Addiction}} | ||
The separation of ''freedom of action'' from ''freedom of will'' is demonstrated in addiction. An unwilling addict has identified withdrawal as desirable but finds themselves unable to enforce that action.<ref name=drunk/> [[Brain imaging]] of addicts and non-addicts show differences in brain activity and can relate the process of addiction to a reprogramming of the brain's handling of [[dopamine]] that can be reversed only with a very prolonged and multipronged therapy.<ref name=dopamine/> | |||
{|align="center" style="width:90%;font-size:97%;" | {|align="center" style="width:90%;font-size:97%;" | ||
|- | |- | ||
|<font face="Gill Sans MT">"Most PET ([[Positron emission tomography|Positron Emission Tomography]]) studies of drug addiction have concentrated on the brain dopamine (DA) system, since this is considered to be the neurotransmitter system through which most drugs of abuse exert their reinforcing effects. A reinforcer is operationally defined as an event that increases the probability of a subsequent response, and drugs of abuse are considered to be much stronger reinforcers than natural reinforcers (''e.g.'' sex and food). The brain DA system also regulates motivation and drive for everyday activities. These imaging studies have revealed that acute and chronic drug consumption have different effects on proteins involved involved in DA synaptic transmission. ... chronic drug consumption results in marked decrease in DA activity which persists months after detoxification and which is associated with deregulation of frontal brain regions. "</font> (Volkow ''et al.''<ref name= | |<font face="Gill Sans MT">"Most PET ([[Positron emission tomography|Positron Emission Tomography]]) studies of drug addiction have concentrated on the brain dopamine (DA) system, since this is considered to be the neurotransmitter system through which most drugs of abuse exert their reinforcing effects. A reinforcer is operationally defined as an event that increases the probability of a subsequent response, and drugs of abuse are considered to be much stronger reinforcers than natural reinforcers (''e.g.'' sex and food). The brain DA system also regulates motivation and drive for everyday activities. These imaging studies have revealed that acute and chronic drug consumption have different effects on proteins involved involved in DA synaptic transmission. ... chronic drug consumption results in marked decrease in DA activity which persists months after detoxification and which is associated with deregulation of frontal brain regions. "</font> (Volkow ''et al.''<ref name=Volkow/>) | ||
|} | |} | ||
{|align="center" style="width:90%;font-size:97%;" | {|align="center" style="width:90%;font-size:97%;" | ||
|- | |- | ||
|<font face="Gill Sans MT">"One of the most consistent findings from imaging studies is that of abnormalities in the prefrontal cortex... The prefrontal cortex is involved in decision making and in inhibitory control... Thus its disruption could lead to inadequate decisions that favor immediate rewards over delayed but more favorable responses. It could also account for the impaired control over the intake of the drug even when the addicted subject expresses the desire to refrain from taking the drug. "</font> (Volkow ''et al.''<ref name= | |<font face="Gill Sans MT">"One of the most consistent findings from imaging studies is that of abnormalities in the prefrontal cortex... The prefrontal cortex is involved in decision making and in inhibitory control... Thus its disruption could lead to inadequate decisions that favor immediate rewards over delayed but more favorable responses. It could also account for the impaired control over the intake of the drug even when the addicted subject expresses the desire to refrain from taking the drug. "</font> (Volkow ''et al.''<ref name=Volkow/>) | ||
|} | |} | ||
===Response times=== | |||
Studies of the timing between actions and the conscious decision to act have a bearing upon free will. A subject's declaration of intention to move a finger appears ''after'' the brain has begun to implement the action, suggesting to some that unconsciously the brain has made the decision ''before'' the conscious mental act to do so. Some believe the implication is that free will was not involved in the decision and is an illusion. The first of these experiments reported the brain registered activity related to the move about 0.2 s before movement onset.<ref name=Libet/> However, these authors also found that awareness of action was ''anticipatory'' to activity in the muscle underlying the movement; the entire process resulting in action involves more steps than just the ''onset'' of brain activity.<ref name=Strother/><ref name= Rosenbaum/> | |||
Some argue that placing the question of free will in the context of motor control is too narrow. The objection is that the time scales involved in motor control are very short, and motor control involves a great deal of unconscious action, with much physical movement entirely unconscious and not a matter of intention at all. On that basis "...free will cannot be squeezed into time frames of 150-350 ms; free will is a longer term phenomenon" and free will is a higher level activity that "cannot be captured in a description of neural activity or of muscle activation..." <ref name=Gallagher/> | |||
The bearing of timing results upon notions of free will appears complex, and remains a topic of discussion. | |||
==Emotion== | |||
{{Main|Emotion}} | |||
From the perspective of [[evolutionary psychology]], emotions evolved in humans in response to environmental challenges, and serve to organize human responses according to success in handling ancestral experience:<ref name=Tooby/> | |||
{|align="center" style="width:90%;font-size:97%;" | |||
| | |||
<font face="Gill Sans MT">"an emotion is a superordinate program whose function is to direct the activities and interactions of many subprograms, including those governing perception, ...categorization and conceptual frameworks,...communication processes, and the recalibration of probability estimates, situation assessments... ." | |||
"All cognitive programs [...] are sometimes mistaken for homunculi,<ref> | |||
''Note:'' A ''humunculus'' is a little person inside the head that carries out mental functions. | |||
</ref> that is, entities endowed with free will. A homunculus scans the environment and freely chooses successful actions. ... It is the task of cognitive psychologists to replace theories that implicitly posit such an impossible entity with theories that can be implemented as fixed programs with open parameters." | |||
"Just as a computer can have an hierarchy of programs, some of which control the activation of others, the human mind can as well. Far from being internal free agents, these programs have an unchanging structure regardless of the needs of the individual or his or here circumstances because they were designed to create states that worked well in ancestral situations, regardless of their consequences in the present."</font> John Tooby and Leda Cosmides: ''Conceptual foundations of evolutionary psychology''<ref name=Tooby/> | |||
|} | |||
Other than undefined "open parameters", perhaps related to "recalibrations", these words leave little room for the effects found in [[Behaviorism|behavioral psychology]], [[cognitive psychology]], and the field of [[developmental psychology]] associated with the names of [[Jean Piaget]] and [[Lev Vygotsky]], which find much room for environmental factors arising during the development of each individual.<ref name=Lerner/> The field of evolutionary psychology is marked by some [[Evolutionary psychology controversy|heated controversy]]. | |||
Although evolutionary psychologists attempt to understand the organization of the mind and brain based upon how they arose, it is hampered by the observation that different species arose in different environments with different responses, making cross-species comparisons very difficult.<ref name=Silverman/> | |||
==Epigenetics== | |||
{{Main|Epigenetics}} | |||
"Once nurture seemed clearly distinct from nature. Now it appears that our diets and lifestyles can change the expression of our genes. How? By influencing a network of chemical switches within our cells collectively known as the epigenome."<ref name=PBS/> Various mechanisms for transference of such environmental response to the next generation are under study.<ref name=Liu/><ref name=Gorelick/> In the context of free will, these mechanisms indicate pathways at a very basic level that can change the programming even of identical twins, and even that of successive generations. Not free will, but certainly adaptivity and originality of response in populations. | |||
==Summary== | ==Summary== | ||
The various notions of ''free will'' conflict, but involve many of the same elements. These matters have been argued for | The various notions of ''free will'' conflict, but involve many of the same elements. These matters have been argued for millennia, and their resolution may depend upon developing a better understanding of what actually goes on in the [[Brain#Mind_and_brain|brain]].<ref name=Freeman/> | ||
{|align="center" style="width:90%;font-size:97%;" | {|align="center" style="width:90%;font-size:97%;" | ||
|- | |- | ||
|<font face="Gill Sans MT">"Although strong advances are being made in analyzing the dynamics of the limbic system and its centerpieces, the entorhinal [[Cerebral cortex|cortex]] and the [[hippocampus]], their self-organized spatial patterns, their precise intentional contents, and their mechanisms of formation in relation to intentional action are still unknown."</font> (Walter J. Freeman, ''Consciousness, intentionality and causality''<ref name=Freeman/>) | |<font face="Gill Sans MT">"Although strong advances are being made in analyzing the dynamics of the limbic system and its centerpieces, the entorhinal [[Cerebral cortex|cortex]] and the [[hippocampus]], their self-organized spatial patterns, their precise intentional contents, and their mechanisms of formation in relation to intentional action are still unknown."</font> (Walter J. Freeman, ''Consciousness, intentionality and causality''<ref name=Freeman/>) | ||
|} | |} | ||
In popular accounts of this subject, the same modern developments are used as new wine in old bottles. On one hand, we have K. E. Stanovitch's ''The Robot's Rebellion: Finding Meaning in the Age of Darwin'', which advances the view that decisions are possible | In popular accounts of this subject, the same modern developments are used as new wine in old bottles. On one hand, we have K. E. Stanovitch's ''The Robot's Rebellion: Finding Meaning in the Age of Darwin'', which advances the view that decisions are possible that transcend mere "instrumental rationality", using goals "keyed to the life interest of the vehicle" to replace unreflective "gut" instincts originating from our genetically programmed autonomous systems.<ref name=Stanovitch/> On the other hand we have books like Sam Harris' ''Free Will'',<ref name=Harris/> and D.M. Wagener's ''The Illusion of Conscious Will'',<ref name=Wegner/> that take the view that consciousness is completely illusory, and old-fashioned determinism is completely correct. | ||
At an individual level, perhaps we can be viewed as complex machines with built-in goals sought using algorithms for survival, which adapt to experience. The conscious monitoring of some aspects of this reprogramming may generate feelings of mental control over our individual destinies even though these feelings may be illusory. Our survival depends upon the execution of ancestral programming that includes some adaptivity, and our mental states may be analogous to a debugger watching the evolution of some code. | |||
The occurrence of mutations introduces a random aspect. Unusual circumstances occur due to random events, provoking new responses. New types of individual arise that exhibit novel reactions even to mundane environmental factors. These novelties may permit (or even force) individuals and societies to explore new avenues. Although once a new path is initiated, evolutionary programming and natural law exert their influences, events proceed with a complexity that defies prediction. | |||
A broader approach to free will is based upon the idea that science is a discipline with a limited field of study, and its methods have been developed to deal with a particular subject matter with particular views of what constitutes "explanation" and "valid data", views that have yet to be generalized to deal with a broader subject matter. According to Mumford, for example, the success in treating the universe as a machine has blinded us today to what was well understood in antiquity, namely, that life is more complicated than that.<ref name=Mumford/> This view is consistent with some philosophers of science, who point out that the human practice of science involves judgements and evaluations that are not scientifically based.<ref name=Kuhn/> From this perspective, the notion that free will cannot exist because man is a machine, is simply myopia. | |||
==References== | ==References== | ||
{{reflist |refs= | {{reflist |refs= | ||
<ref name=AI>{{cite book |title=Mind Design II: Philosophy, Psychology, and Artificial Intelligence |author=John R Searle |editor=John Haugeland, ed |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=TIC1mzIQZMIC&pg=PA203&lpg=PA203 |pages=p. 203 |isbn=0262082594 |year=1997 |publisher=MIT Press |edition=2nd ed}} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=analogy> | <ref name=analogy> | ||
{{cite journal |journal=Nature |date=April 1, 1933 |pages=p. 457 ''ff'' |title=Light and Life |author=Niels Bohr |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=4RStj6dJDSgC&pg=PA28&lpg=PA28}} Full text on line at [http://www23.us.archive.org/stream/AtomicPhysicsHumanKnowledge/Bohr-AtomicPhysicsHumanKnowledge_djvu.txt us.archive.org]. | {{cite journal |journal=Nature |date=April 1, 1933 |pages=p. 457 ''ff'' |title=Light and Life |author=Niels Bohr |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=4RStj6dJDSgC&pg=PA28&lpg=PA28}} Full text on line at [http://www23.us.archive.org/stream/AtomicPhysicsHumanKnowledge/Bohr-AtomicPhysicsHumanKnowledge_djvu.txt us.archive.org]. | ||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Atlan> | |||
{{cite book |title=Henri Atlan: Selected Writings |chapter=Chapter 2: Intentional self-organization: Emergence and reduction, toward a physical theory of reduction |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=BpOhzxMuD6wC&pg=PA70&lpg=PA70 |pages=pp. 70 ''ff'' |editor=Todd Meyers, Stefanos Geroulanos |author=Henri Atlan |publisher=Fordham University Press |year=2011 |edition= Translation of ''Thesis'' 11 52 (February 1998): 5-34 }} | |||
</ref> | </ref> | ||
Line 108: | Line 329: | ||
<ref name=Balaguer> | <ref name=Balaguer> | ||
{{cite book |title=Free Will As an Open Scientific Problem |author=Mark Balaguer |pages=pp. 1 ''ff'' |chapter=Introduction |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=06VcZ6dtswUC&pg=PA3 |isbn=0262013541 |author=Mark Balaguer |publisher=MIT Press |year=2009}} | {{cite book |title=Free Will As an Open Scientific Problem |author=Mark Balaguer |pages=pp. 1 ''ff'' |chapter=Introduction |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=06VcZ6dtswUC&pg=PA3 |isbn=0262013541 |author=Mark Balaguer |publisher=MIT Press |year=2009}} | ||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Baumeister> | |||
{{cite book |title=Oxford Handbook of Human Action |chapter=Chapter 23: Free Willpower: A limited resource theory of volition, choice and self-regulation |author=Roy F Baumeister, Matthew T Galliot, Dianne M Tice |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=zFP1AZYlNmcC&pg=PA487&lpg=PA487 |pages=pp. 487 ''ff'' |editor=Ezequiel Morsella, John A. Bargh, Peter M. Gollwitzer |isbn= 0195309987 |year=2008 |publisher=Oxford University Press |edition=Volume 2 of Social Cognition and Social Neuroscience }} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Bargh> | |||
{{cite web |title=Free will is un-natural |author=John A Bargh |url=http://www.yale.edu/acmelab/articles/FreeWillIsUnnatural.pdf |accessdate=2012-08-21 |date=2007-011-16 }} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Bohr> | |||
{{cite web |author=Neils Bohr |title= The Atomic Theory and the Fundamental Principles underlying the Description of Nature; ''Based on a lecture to the Scandinavian Meeting of Natural Scientists and published in Danish in Fysisk Tidsskrift in 1929. First published in English in 1934 by Cambridge University Press.''|work=The Information Philosopher, dedicated to the new information philosophy |url=http://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/bohr/fundamental_principles.html |publisher=Robert O. Doyle, publisher |accessdate=2012-09-14}} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Britannica> | |||
{{cite web |quote=Arguments for free will are based on the subjective experience of freedom |url=http://www.britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/218436/free-will |title=Free will |work=Encyclopedia Britannica |date=5-28-2013}} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Caruso> | |||
{{cite book |title=Free Will and Consciousness: A Determinist Account of the Illusion of Free Will |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=TvvaM77QC44C&pg=PA8#v=onepage&q&f=false |page =8 |author=Gregg D Caruso |isbn=0739171364 |year=2012 |publisher=Lexington Books| quote=One of the strongest supports for the free choice thesis is the unmistakable intuition of virtually every human being that he is free to make the choices he does and that the deliberations leading to those choices are also free flowing..}} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Chater> | |||
{{cite book |author=Nick Chater |chapter=Chapter 4: Building blocks of human decision making |title=Evolution and the Mechanisms of Decision Making |editor= Peter Hammerstein, Jeffrey R. Stevens, eds |publisher=MIT Press |year=2012 |pages=53-68 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=vzIII2PqWqoC&pg=PA53 |isbn=9780262018081}} | |||
</ref> | </ref> | ||
<ref name=Chrysippus> | <ref name=Chrysippus> | ||
{{cite book |title=The Cambridge History of Hellenistic Philosophy |publisher=Cambridge University Press |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=9lRD6feR3hEC&pg=PA529 |pages=p. 529 |chapter=Chapter VI: The Chyrsippean notion of fate: soft determinism |author=Keimpe Algra |isbn=0521250285 |year=1999}} | {{cite book |title=The Cambridge History of Hellenistic Philosophy |publisher=Cambridge University Press |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=9lRD6feR3hEC&pg=PA529 |pages=p. 529 |chapter=Chapter VI: The Chyrsippean notion of fate: soft determinism |author=Keimpe Algra |isbn=0521250285 |year=1999}} | ||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=computer> | |||
For example, see the discussion in {{cite book |title=50 Years of Artificial Intelligence: Essays Dedicated to the 50th Anniversary of Artificial Intelligence |chapter=What can ''AI'' get from neuroscience? |author=Steve M. Potter |pages=pp. 174 'ff'' |editor=Max Lungarella, Fumiya Iida, Josh Bongard, eds |isbn=3540772952 |year=2008 |publisher=Springer |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=vin0j1Z4fZUC&pg=PA174}} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Copland> | |||
{{cite book |author=Aaron Copland |title=Music and Imagination |quote=It [music] is at the same time outside and away from us and inside and part of us. |page=10 |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=fizovlYL-jIC&pg=PA10 |chapter=The Charles Elliot Norton lectures, 1951-52 |isbn=0674589157 |year=1980 |publisher=Harvard University Press }} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Cornman> | |||
{{cite book |chapter=Chapter 3: The problem of freedom and determinism |pages=pp. 91 ''ff'' |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=cRHegYZgyfUC&pg=PA122&dq=%22if+I+do+A,+and+determinism+is+true,+then%22&hl=en&sa=X&ei=pDxfVZPxJoXxoASp2IHwCw&ved=0CB4Q6AEwAA#v=onepage&q=%22if%20I%20do%20A%2C%20and%20determinism%20is%20true%2C%20then%22&f=false |isbn=9780872201248 |publisher=Hackett Publishing |year=1992 |author=James W. Cornman, Keith Lehrer, George Sotiros Pappas |title=Philosophical Problems and Arguments: An Introduction |quote=If determinism is true, and I perform action ''A'', then not only is it true that nothing else could have happened, it is also true that nothing else could have happened because of conditions over which I had no control.}} | |||
</ref> | </ref> | ||
Line 117: | Line 374: | ||
{{cite book |title=Darwin's Screens: Evolutionary Aesthetics, Time and Sexual Display in the Cinema |chapter=Intelligent machines and created life forms |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=zZcHElioE3QC&pg=PA65 |pages =pp. 65 ''ff'' |author=Barbara Creed |year= 2009 |publisher=Academic Monographs |isbn=0522857094}} | {{cite book |title=Darwin's Screens: Evolutionary Aesthetics, Time and Sexual Display in the Cinema |chapter=Intelligent machines and created life forms |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=zZcHElioE3QC&pg=PA65 |pages =pp. 65 ''ff'' |author=Barbara Creed |year= 2009 |publisher=Academic Monographs |isbn=0522857094}} | ||
</ref> | </ref> | ||
<ref name=Csikszentmihalyi> | <ref name=Csikszentmihalyi> | ||
A paraphrase of a statement by {{cite book |title=Flow: The psychology of optimal experience |author=Mihaly Csikszentmihalyi |isbn=0060920432 |url= | A paraphrase of a statement by {{cite book |title=Flow: The psychology of optimal experience |author=Mihaly Csikszentmihalyi |isbn=0060920432 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=v2AVz3gf-F4C&pg=PT38&dq=%22we+should+also+recognize+that+the+way+in+which+consciousness+works%22&hl=en&sa=X&ei=JTZfVcWhM8XJogTk14HwDg&ved=0CCMQ6AEwAQ#v=onepage&q=%22we%20should%20also%20recognize%20that%20the%20way%20in%20which%20consciousness%20works%22&f=false |year=1990 |publisher=Harper & Row |pages=p. 24 |quote=Consciousness has developed the ability to override its genetic instructions and to set its own independent course of action}} | ||
</ref> | </ref> | ||
Line 136: | Line 392: | ||
<ref name=dopamine> | <ref name=dopamine> | ||
{{cite book |title= | One mechanism of addiction is the interruption of recycling of dopamine into a transmitting neuron by blocking of ''dopamine transporters'', resulting in a build-up of dopamine in the synapse. See, for example, {{cite book |title=Addiction Treatment |author=Katherine Van Wormer, Diane Rae Davis |chapter=Caption to Figure 3.4 |pages=p. 154 |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=Q98TT5i4BG0C&pg=PA153&lpg=PA154 |isbn=0840029160 |publisher=Cengage Learning |edition =3rd ed |year=2012}} For a discussion of therapy, see for example {{cite book |title=Pathophysiology: Concepts of Altered Health States |author=Carol Mattson Porth |isbn=1605473901 |edition=8th ed |year=2008 |publisher=Lippincott Williams & Wilkins |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=2-MFXOEG0lcC&pg=PA1316&lpg=PA1316 |pages=p. 1316 ''ff'' |chapter=Disorders of Abuse and Addiction}} Link is to the Canadian edition. | ||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=drunk> | |||
How can I tell if I have a drinking problem? One determinant is: "If you sometimes get drunk when you fully intend to stay sober." {{cite book |title=The Complete Encyclopedia of Medicine & Health |editor=Johannes P. Schade, ed |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=j8DuEHxSCU4C&pg=PA134 |pages=p. 134 |chapter=Alcoholism: Questions and answers |isbn=1601360010 |year=2006 |publisher=Foreign Media Group}} | |||
</ref> | </ref> | ||
<ref name=Duhem> | <ref name=Duhem> | ||
{{cite book |title=The Aim and Structure of Physical Theory |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=5mVPK7QBdTkC&pg=PA21 |pages=p. 21 |publisher=Princeton University Press |year=1991 |isbn=069102524X |author=Pierre Maurice Marie Duhem}} | {{cite book |title=The Aim and Structure of Physical Theory |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=5mVPK7QBdTkC&pg=PA21 |pages=p. 21 |publisher=Princeton University Press |year=1991 |isbn=069102524X |author=Pierre Maurice Marie Duhem}} | ||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Eagleman> | |||
Morality and the brain; an interview with neuroscientist David Eagleman by David Edmonds and Nigel Warburton: {{cite web |url=http://hwcdn.libsyn.com/p/8/3/6/836916f7469834b7/David_Eagleman_on_Morality_and_the_Brain.mp3?c_id=3279169&expiration=1393259206&hwt=beb44622f67f089b88228cb1b21b441b |accessdate=February, 2014 |date=May 22, 2011 |publisher=[http://philosophybites.com/about_us.html Published by philosophy bites], and the [http://www.philosophy.sas.ac.uk/ Institute of Philosophy] |author=David Eagleman |title=Morality and the brain}} "It turns out that if free will exists, it's really a bit player in what's going on in the brain." (@ 4:44 minutes) | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=ElBizri> | |||
{{cite book |title=The Phenomenological Quest Between Avicenna and Heidegger |author=Nader El-Bizri |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=DEVc6o-mOp4C&pg=PA97&lpg=PA97 |pages=pp. 97-98 |isbn= 1586840053 |year=2000 |publisher=Global Academic Publishing}} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Ellis> | |||
{{cite book |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=1wL3Dqze56UC&pg=PA48&lpg=PA48 |pages=pp. 48-49 |chapter=Efferent brain processes and the enactive approach to consciousness |edition=Reprint from ''Journal of Consciousness Studies'', '''7''' (4)2000, pp. 40-50 |author=Ralph D Ellis |title=How to Solve the Mind-- Body Problem |editor=Nicholas Humphrey, ed |isbn=0907845088 |year=2000 |publisher=Imprint Academic}} | |||
</ref> | </ref> | ||
<ref name=evolution> | <ref name=evolution> | ||
This field is sometimes called ''Darwinian engineering'' or ''evolutionary robotics''. See for example, {{cite book |title=New Horizons in Evolutionary Robotics: Extended Contributions from the 2009 EvoDeRob Workshop |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=kZVY8rzwvY0C&pg=PA3&lpg=PA3 |pages=pp. 3 ''ff'' |author=Stéphane Doncieux, Jean-Baptiste Mouret, Nicolas Bredechte, Vincent Padois |chapter=Chapter 1: Evolutionary robotics: exploring new horizons |editor=Stéphane Doncieux, ed |isbn=3642182712 |year=2011 |publisher=Springer}} | This field is sometimes called ''Darwinian engineering'' or ''evolutionary robotics''. See for example, {{cite book |title=New Horizons in Evolutionary Robotics: Extended Contributions from the 2009 EvoDeRob Workshop |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=kZVY8rzwvY0C&pg=PA3&lpg=PA3 |pages=pp. 3 ''ff'' |author=Stéphane Doncieux, Jean-Baptiste Mouret, Nicolas Bredechte, Vincent Padois |chapter=Chapter 1: Evolutionary robotics: exploring new horizons |editor=Stéphane Doncieux, ed |isbn=3642182712 |year=2011 |publisher=Springer}} | ||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=feedback> | |||
{{cite book |title=The Interactional Instinct: The Evolution and Acquisition of Language |chapter=Feedback and circular causality |author= Namhee Lee, Lisa Mikesell, Anna Dina L. Joaquin, Andrea W. Mates, John H. Schumann |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=wVxc0SkDFtUC&pg=PA26&lpg=PA26 |pages=pp. 26 ''ff'' |isbn=0195384237 |publisher=Oxford University Press |year=2009}} | |||
</ref> | </ref> | ||
Line 154: | Line 430: | ||
{{cite book |title=Does Consciousness Cause Behavior? |editor=Susan Pockett, WP Banks, Shaun Gallagher, eds |chapter=Consciousness, intentionality and causality |author=Walter J Freeman |publisher=MIT Press |date =2009 |isbn=0262512572 |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=G5CaTnNksgkC&pg=PA88&lpg=PA88 |pages=p. 88}} | {{cite book |title=Does Consciousness Cause Behavior? |editor=Susan Pockett, WP Banks, Shaun Gallagher, eds |chapter=Consciousness, intentionality and causality |author=Walter J Freeman |publisher=MIT Press |date =2009 |isbn=0262512572 |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=G5CaTnNksgkC&pg=PA88&lpg=PA88 |pages=p. 88}} | ||
</ref> | </ref> | ||
<ref name=Gallagher0> | |||
"All normal humans experience a kind of basic, on-the-ground certainty that we, our conscious selves, cause our own voluntary acts." from {{cite book |title=Does Consciousness Cause Behavior? |author=Susan Pockett, William P. Banks, Shaun Gallagher |chapter=Introduction |editor=Susan Pockett, William P. Banks, Shaun Gallagher, eds |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=G5CaTnNksgkC&pg=PA1 |pages=p. 1 |isbn=0262512572 |publisher=MIT Press |year=2009 }} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Gallagher> | |||
{{cite book |title=Does Consciousness Cause Behavior? |author=Shaun Gallagher |chapter=Chapter 6: Where's the action? Epiphenomenalism and the problem of free will |editor= |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=G5CaTnNksgkC&pg=PA119 |pages=pp. 119-121 |isbn=0262512572 |publisher=MIT Press |year=2009 |editor=Susan Pockett, William P. Banks, Shaun Gallagher, eds}} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Goldstein> | <ref name=Goldstein> | ||
An historical outline of the evolution of cognitive psychology and its relation to behaviorism is found in {{cite book |title=Cognitive Psychology: Connecting Mind, Research, and Everyday Experience |author= E. Bruce Goldstein |chapter= Chapter 1: Introduction to Cognitive Psychology |pages=pp. 1 ''ff'' |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=XkBoSZ0O1bwC&printsec=frontcover |isbn=0495095575 |year=2008 |publisher=Cengage Learning |edition=2nd ed}} | An historical outline of the evolution of cognitive psychology and its relation to behaviorism is found in {{cite book |title=Cognitive Psychology: Connecting Mind, Research, and Everyday Experience |author= E. Bruce Goldstein |chapter= Chapter 1: Introduction to Cognitive Psychology |pages=pp. 1 ''ff'' |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=XkBoSZ0O1bwC&printsec=frontcover |isbn=0495095575 |year=2008 |publisher=Cengage Learning |edition=2nd ed}} | ||
</ref> | |||
<ref name= Goldstein0> | |||
{{cite book |author= E. Bruce Goldstein |title=Sensation and Perception |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=2tW91BWeNq4C&pg=PA39 |pages=p. 39 |quote=Solving the hard problem of consciousness involves determining how physiological processes such as ions flowing across the nerve membrane ''cause'' us to have experiences. |isbn=0495601497 |edition=10th ed |publisher=Cengage Learning |year=2010}} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Gorelick> | |||
{{cite journal |url=http://http-server.carleton.ca/~rgorelic/Publications/Gorelick%20%282004%29%20Med.%20Hyp.%2062%282%29%3B%20299-303.pdf |title=Neo-Lamarckian medicine |author=Root Gorelick |journal=Medical Hypotheses |volume=62 |pages=pp. 299-303 |year=2004 |doi=10.1016/S0306-9877(03)00329-3}} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=GStrawson> | |||
"The freedom in question is a property, real or imagined, that nearly all adult human beings...believe themselves to possess. To say that one doesn't understand what it is, is to claim to lack the most basic understanding of the society one lives in, and such a claim is not believable." from {{cite book |title=Freedom and Belief |author= Galen Strawson |pages=p. 2 |isbn=0199247501 |year=2010 |publisher=Oxford University Press |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=DjB9AM0tupMC}} Quoted by [http://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/philosophers/strawsong/ The Information Philosopher] and accessible on-line in Amazon's [http://www.amazon.com/Freedom-Belief-Galen-Strawson/dp/0199247501/ref=sr_1_1?s=books&ie=UTF8&qid=1347204067&sr=1-1&keywords=0199247501#reader_0199247501 'look inside' feature]. | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Haken> | |||
{{cite book |title=Information and Self-Organization: A Macroscopic Approach to Complex Systems |author=Hermann Haken |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=tAfj4-xzyGwC&pg=PA25&lpg=PA25 |pages=p. 25 |isbn=3540330216 |edition=3rd ed |publisher=Springer |year=2006}} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Harbecke> | |||
{{cite book |title=Mental Causation: Investigating the Mind's Powers in a Natural World |author=Jens Harbecke |isbn=3938793945 |publisher=Ontos Verlag |year=2009 |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=5pQxzzc6NP0C&printsec=frontcover}} | |||
</ref> | </ref> | ||
<ref name=Harris> | <ref name=Harris> | ||
{{cite book |url= | {{cite book |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=lvsiwZFucKoC&pg=PA5&dq=%22causes+of+which+we+are+unaware+and+over+which+we+exert+no+conscious+control%22&hl=en&sa=X&ei=xY5gVbPfIIK1oQS8k4GQBA&ved=0CCkQ6AEwAg#v=onepage&q=%22causes%20of%20which%20we%20are%20unaware%20and%20over%20which%20we%20exert%20no%20conscious%20control%22&f=false |author=Sam Harris |title=Free Will |pages=p. 5 |isbn=1451683405 |year=2012 |publisher=Simon and Schuster}} | ||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Harris2> | |||
{{cite book |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=iRpkNcRt1IcC&pg=PA20&dq=puppet+%22+loves+his+strings%22&hl=en&sa=X&ei=XpBgVaz-I82pogT9gYGoCg&ved=0CB4Q6AEwAA#v=onepage&q=puppet%20%22%20loves%20his%20strings%22&f=false |author=Sam Harris |title=Free Will |isbn=1451683405 |year=2012 |pages=p. 20 |publisher=Simon and Schuster}} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Higgins> | |||
For a discussion, see {{cite book |title=The Big Questions: A Short Introduction to Philosophy |author=Robert C. Solomon, Kathleen M. Higgins |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=ekh2AKqXdqgC&pg=PA232 |pages=p. 232 |isbn=0495595152 |publisher=Cengage Learning |chapter=Free will and determinism|year=2009 |edition=8th}} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Holton> | |||
{{cite book |title=Willing, Wanting, Waiting |author=Richard Holton |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=dpVOpqhmV3YC&pg=PR64 |quote=A quick and effective way to generate a conviction in undergraduates that they have free will is to get them to choose...The undergraduates have in the first instance an experience: an experience of doing something, namely, making a choice...they could have chosen any of a number of options and hence that they are, in that respect, unmoved movers. |chapter=First experience of freedom: choice |publisher=Oxford University Press |year=2009 |isbn=9780191607547}} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Hutto> | |||
{{cite book |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=pAj-96LlBuMC&pg=PA6&dq=%22Variables+in+the+environment+influence%22&hl=en&sa=X&ei=-VBGVbblPI_xoAT_9IHwBw&ved=0CCcQ6AEwAA#v=onepage&q=%22Variables%20in%20the%20environment%20influence%22&f=false |quote=Variables in the environment influence and are influenced by variables in the brain and the non-neural body in a recurrent manner, making it impossible to conceive of these as linear relations holding between inputs and outputs...There is no way to isolate properly mentality-constituting 'inner' organismic responses from 'outer' ones that allegedly stand over and against the former as mere causal contributions from the environment. |title=Radicalizing Enactivism: Basic Minds Without Content |author=Daniel D. Hutto, Erik Myin |isbn= 9780262018548 |publisher=MIT Press |year=2013 |pages=p. 6}} | |||
</ref> | </ref> | ||
<ref name=illusion> | <ref name=illusion> | ||
Quote from {{cite book |url=http://www.google.com/search?tbo=p&tbm=bks&q=consciousness%2Bplays%2Ba%2Bsmaller%2Brole%2Bin%2Bhuman%2Blife+intitle:User+intitle:illusion&num=10 |title=The user illusion: Cutting consciousness down to size |author=Tor Nørretranders |isbn= | Quote from {{cite book |url=http://www.google.com/search?tbo=p&tbm=bks&q=consciousness%2Bplays%2Ba%2Bsmaller%2Brole%2Bin%2Bhuman%2Blife+intitle:User+intitle:illusion&num=10 |title=The user illusion: Cutting consciousness down to size |author=Tor Nørretranders |isbn=9780140230123 |chapter=Preface |pages=p. ''ix'' |publisher=Penguin Books |year=1998 |edition=Jonathan Sydenham translation of ''Maerk verden'' 1991 ed }} | ||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Kandel> | |||
This quote is from: {{cite book |pages=p. 9 |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=PFnRwWXzypgC&pg=PA9&lpg=PA9 |author=Eric R. Kandel |isbn=0393329372 |publisher=WW Norton |year=2007 |title=In Search of Memory: The Emergence of a New Science of Mind}} However, the same language can be found in dozens of sources. Some philosophers object to the unsupported statement of such conjectures, for example, observing that ''consciousness'' has yet to be shown to be a ''process'' at all, never mind a biological process. See {{cite book |title=Wittgenstein and the Human Form of Life |author=Oswald Hanfling |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=TRIkWPqy-JgC&pg=PA108&lpg=PA108 |pages=pp. 108-109 |isbn=0415256453 |publisher=Psychology Press |year=2002}} | |||
</ref> | </ref> | ||
<ref name=Kant> | <ref name=Kant> | ||
{{cite book |title=Kant's Critique of Pure Reason: Critical Essays |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=an6gikoVw18C&pg=PA240 |pages=pp. 240 ''ff'' |author=Allen W Wood |editor=Patricia Kitcher, ed |year=1998 |publisher=Rowman & Littlefield |isbn=0847689174}} | {{cite book |title=Kant's Critique of Pure Reason: Critical Essays |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=an6gikoVw18C&pg=PA240 |pages=pp. 240 ''ff'' |author=Allen W Wood |editor=Patricia Kitcher, ed |year=1998 |publisher=Rowman & Littlefield |isbn=0847689174}} | ||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Kalat> | |||
For a brief historical rundown, see {{cite book |title=Biological Psychology |author=James W. Kalat |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=ZlSbk5rUY60C&pg=PA7 |pages=p. 7 |isbn=0495603007 |year=2008 |publisher=Cengage Learning |edition=10th ed}} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Kelso> | |||
{{cite book |title=Dynamic Patterns: The Self-Organization of Brain and Behavior |author=J. A. Scott Kelso |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=zpjejjytkiIC&pg=PA16&lpg=PA16 |pages=p. 16 |quote=An order parameter is created by the correlation between the parts, but in turn influences the behavior of the parts. This is what we mean by ''circular causality''. |isbn=0262611317 |year=1995 |publisher=MIT Press}} Kelso also says (p. 9): "But add a few more parts interlaced together and very quickly it becomes impossible to treat the system in terms of feedback circuits. In such complex systems, ... the concept of feedback is inadequate.[...] there is no reference state with which feedback can be compared and no place where comparison operations are performed." | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Kozielecki> | |||
{{cite book |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=LQc-zQoOuFMC&pg=PA11 |pages=p. 11 |chapter=§1.3 The structure of psychological decision theory |title=Psychological Decision Theory |author=J. Kozielecki |isbn= 9789027710512 |year=1981 |publisher=Springer Science & Business Media}} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Kuhn> | |||
{{cite book |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=3eP5Y_OOuzwC&q=%22conversions+occur+not+despite+the+fact+that+scientists%22+#v=snippet&q=%22conversions%20occur%20not%20despite%20the%20fact%20that%20scientists%22&f=false |title=The Structure of Scientific Revolutions |author=Thomas S. Kuhn |isbn= 9780226458083 |year=1996 |pages= |publisher=University of Chicago Press |quote=Still,...that paradigm change cannot be justified by proof, is not to say that no arguments are relevant, or that scientists cannot be persuaded to change their minds...Furthermore, these conversions occur not despite the fact that scientists are human but because they are. |pages=p. 51}} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Lamont> | |||
"One of the strongest supports for the free choice thesis is the unmistakable intuition of virtually every human being that he is free to make the choices he does and that the deliberations leading to those choices are also free flowing." [http://books.google.com/books?id=iWu4AAAAIAAJ&q=Corliss+Lamont+%22unmistakable+intuition+of+virtually+%22&dq=Corliss+Lamont+%22unmistakable+intuition+of+virtually+%22&hl=en&sa=X&ei=Kg24UNfCBo-MigKC6IDwBA&ved=0CDMQ6AEwAQ Corliss Lamont] as quoted by {{cite book |title=Free Will and Consciousness: A Determinist Account of the Illusion of Free Will |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=TvvaM77QC44C&pg=PA8#v=onepage&q&f=false |pages=p. 8 |author=Gregg D Caruso |isbn=0739171364 |year=2012 |publisher=Lexington Books}} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Lerner> | |||
{{cite book |author=Willis F Overton |chapter=Chapter 1: Development across the life span |editor= Lerner, M. Ann Easterbrooks, Jayanthi Mistry |edition=Volume 6 of Handbook of Psychology |title=Handbook of Psychology, Developmental Psychology |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=RhV8wtqPfXkC&pg=PA13&lpg=PA13 |pages=pp. 13 ''ff'' |isbn=0471264474 |year=2003 |publisher=John Wiley & Sons}} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Libet> | |||
{{cite journal |title=Time of conscious intention to act in relation to onset of cerebral activity (readiness-potential). |author=Benjamin Libet ''et al.'' |journal=Brain |year=1983 |volume=106 |pages=623-642 |url=http://trans-techresearch.net/wp-content/uploads/2012/02/Brain-1983-LIBET.pdf}} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Liu> | |||
{{cite web |title=Like father like son. A fresh review of the inheritance of acquired characteristics |author=Yongsheng Liu |url=http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC1973965/ |work=EMBO Reports |date=September 2007|accesdate=2012-09-05}} The European Molecular Biology Organization EMBO Rep. 2007 September; '''8'''(9): 798-803. PMC1973965 DOI=10.1038/sj.embor.7401060 | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Loewer> | |||
{{cite book |title=Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Volume 6 |editor=Edward Craig, general editor |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=G3UBxqkkCX8C&pg=PA310 |pages=p. 310 |isbn=0415073103 |publisher=Oxford University Press |author=Barry Loewer}} referring to Nagel ([http://www.cs.helsinki.fi/u/ahyvarin/teaching/niseminar4/Nagel_WhatIsItLikeToBeABat.pdf What is it like to be a bat?], 1974) and to Jackson ([http://web.ics.purdue.edu/~drkelly/JacksonWhatMaryDidntKnow1986.pdf What Mary didn't know], 1986) | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=LTD> | |||
{{cite journal |journal=The American Journal of Psychiatry |date=May 01, 2011 |title=Deep brain stimulation for treatment-resistant depression: Follow-up after 3 to 6 years |author=Sidney H Kennedy ''et al.'' |url=http://ajp.psychiatryonline.org/article.aspx?articleid=106984 |volume=168 |issue=5|accessdate=2012-09-04}} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Mackenzie> | |||
{{cite book |author=Catriona Mackenzie |chapter=Chapter 21: Autonomy |title=The Routledge Companion to Bioethics |editor= John D. Arras, Elizabeth Fenton, Rebecca Kukla, eds |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=vUa2BQAAQBAJ&pg=PA277 |pages=pp. 277 ''ff'' |isbn= 9781136644849 |year=2014 |publisher=Routledge}} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Michelangelo> | |||
As translated with artistic license by Eric Scigliano: | |||
:::"The finest artist can't conceive a thought | |||
:::that the marble itself does not bind | |||
:::within its shell, waiting to be brought | |||
:::out by the hand that serves the artist's mind." | |||
Poem by Michelangelo; see {{cite book |title=Michelangelo's Mountain: The Quest for Perfection in the Marble Quarries of Carrara |author= Eric Scigliano |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=QKDeyBjXzB8C&pg=PA24&lpg=PA24 |pages=p. 24 |isbn=0743254775 |year=2005 |publisher=Simon & Schuster}} A more literal translation and the original poem is found in {{cite book |author=James M. Saslow |title=The Poetry of Michelangelo: An Annotated Translation |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=c2PSBAnBQxIC&pg=PA302&lpg=PA302 |isbn=0300055099 |pages=p. 302 |chapter=Poem 151 |year=1993 |publisher=Yale University Press}} | |||
</ref> | </ref> | ||
Line 177: | Line 554: | ||
<ref name=Monterosso> | <ref name=Monterosso> | ||
The term ''naïve dualism'' is used by {{cite web |title=Did your brain make you do it? |author=John Monterosso, Barry Schwartz |publisher=New York Times |work=Gray Matter |url=http://www.nytimes.com/2012/07/29/opinion/sunday/neuroscience-and-moral-responsibility.html |date=July 27, 2012 |accessdate=2012-07-29}} | The term ''naïve dualism'' is used by {{cite web |title=Did your brain make you do it? |author=John Monterosso, Barry Schwartz |publisher=New York Times |work=Gray Matter |url=http://www.nytimes.com/2012/07/29/opinion/sunday/neuroscience-and-moral-responsibility.html |date=July 27, 2012 |accessdate=2012-07-29}} | ||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Mumford> | |||
{{cite book |title=The Myth of the Machine - Book 2: The Pentagon of Power |author=Lewis Mumford |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=P8NFAAAAYAAJ&dq=bibliogroup%3A%22The+Myth+of+the+Machine%22&focus=searchwithinvolume&q=Galileo |pages =p. 57 |chapter=Chapter 3 §2: The Crime of Galileo |isbn=9780156716109 |year=1974 |publisher=Harcourt Brace Jovanovich |quote=Galileo committed a crime far graver than any the dignitaries of the Church accused him of; for his real crime was that of trading the totality of human experience...for that minute portion which can observed within a limited time-span and interpreted in terms of mass and motion, while denying importance to the unmediated realities of human experience, from which science itself is only a refined ideological derivative. }} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Nagel0> | |||
{{cite book |title=The Structure of Science: Problems in the Logic of Scientific Explanation |author=Ernest Nagel |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=u6EycHgRfkQC&pg=PA285 |pages =285-292 |chapter=§V: Alternative descriptions of physical state |isbn=0915144719 |year=1999 |publisher=Hackett |edition=2nd }} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Nagel> | |||
{{cite book |title=The Structure of Science: Problems in the Logic of Scientific Explanation |author=Ernest Nagel |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=u6EycHgRfkQC&pg=PA285 |pages =285-292 |chapter=§V: Alternative descriptions of physical state |isbn=0915144719 |year=1999 |publisher=Hackett |edition=2nd }} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=NagelT> | |||
{{cite book |title=The View From Nowhere |author=Thomas Nagel |chapter=Freedom |quote=Nothing that might be a solution has yet been described. This is not a case where there are several possible candidate solutions and we don't know which is correct. It is a case where nothing believable has (to my knowledge) been proposed. |isbn=9780195056440 |year=1989 |publisher=Oxford University Press |page=112 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=5cryOCGb2nEC&pg=PA112&dq=%22Nothing+that+might+be+a+solution+has+yet+been+described%22&hl=en&sa=X&ei=LUpfVaf3KYjHogStqYD4DQ&ved=0CCQQ6AEwAQ#v=onepage&q=%22Nothing%20that%20might%20be%20a%20solution%20has%20yet%20been%20described%22&f=false}} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=NagelT2> | |||
One author's view is found in: {{cite book |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=XYaJg8GZc98C&pg=PA113&dq=%22a+conscious+control+of+action%22+%22cannot+be+analyzed+as+physical+causation+with+an+epiphenomenal+conscious+accompaniment,+%22&hl=en&sa=X&ei=1j9OVaODJI3VoASv-oDoDw&ved=0CB4Q6AEwAA#v=onepage&q=%22a%20conscious%20control%20of%20action%22%20%22cannot%20be%20analyzed%20as%20physical%20causation%20with%20an%20epiphenomenal%20conscious%20accompaniment%2C%20%22&f=false |title=Mind and Cosmos: Why the Materialist Neo-Darwinian Conception of Nature Is Almost Certainly False |author=Thomas Nagel |page=113 |isbn=9780199977192 |year=2012 |publisher=Oxford University Press |quote=I believe that it [my capacity to respond] involves a conscious control of action that cannot be analyzed as physical causation with an epiphenomenal conscious accompaniment, and that it includes some form of free will — }} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Northoff> | |||
A rather extended discussion is provided in {{cite book |title=Philosophy of the Brain: The Brain Problem |author=Georg Northoff |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=r0Bf3lLys6AC&printsec=frontcover |publisher=John Benjamins Publishing |isbn=1588114171 |year=2004 |edition=Volume 52 of Advances in Consciousness Research}} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Northoff2> | |||
{{cite book |title=Philosophy of the Brain: The Brain Problem |author=Georg Northoff |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=CJq4QDixIg0C&pg=PT148&lpg=PT148 |publisher=John Benjamins Publishing |isbn=1588114171 |year=2004 |edition=Volume 52 of Advances in Consciousness Research |pages=pp. 137-139}} | |||
</ref> | </ref> | ||
<ref name=OConnor> | <ref name=OConnor> | ||
{{cite web |title=Free Will |date=Oct 29, 2010 |author=O'Connor, Timothy |url=http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2011/entries/freewill |work=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2011 Edition) |editor=Edward N. Zalta, ed}} | {{cite web |title=Free Will |date=Oct 29, 2010 |author=O'Connor, Timothy |url=http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2011/entries/freewill |work=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2011 Edition) |editor=Edward N. Zalta, ed}} | ||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Peruzzi> | |||
See for example: {{cite book |title=Mind and Causality |chapter=Chapter 5: Mental causation and intentionality in a mind naturalizing theory |author=Sandro Nannini |editor=Alberto Peruzzi, ed |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=zYEPifPTQK4C&pg=PA75&lpg=PA77 |pages=pp. 69 ''ff'' |isbn=1588114759 |publisher=John Benjamins Publishing |year=2004}} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=PBS> | |||
{{cite web |title=Epigenetics |url=http://www.pbs.org/wgbh/nova/body/epigenetics.html |work=Nova Beta |publisher=Produced for PBS Online by WGBH Educational Foundation}} | |||
</ref> | </ref> | ||
<ref name=Pockett> | <ref name=Pockett> | ||
{{cite book|title=Does Consciousness Cause Behavior? |chapter=The neuroscience of movement |author=Susan Pockett |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=G5CaTnNksgkC&pg=PA19&lpg=PA19 |pages=p. 19 |editor=Susan Pockett, WP Banks, Shaun Gallagher, eds |publisher=MIT Press |date =2009 |isbn=0262512572}} | {{cite book|title=Does Consciousness Cause Behavior? |chapter=The neuroscience of movement |author=Susan Pockett |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=G5CaTnNksgkC&pg=PA19&lpg=PA19 |pages=p. 19 |editor=Susan Pockett, WP Banks, Shaun Gallagher, eds |publisher=MIT Press |date =2009 |isbn=0262512572}} | ||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Popper> | |||
{{cite book |title=All Life is Problem Solving |chapter=Notes of a realist on the body-mind problem |author=Karl Raimund Popper |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=Pa3cZYwdq28C&pg=PA26&lpg=PA23 |pages=pp. 23 ''ff'' |isbn=0415174864 |year=1999 |publisher=Psychology Press |quote=The body-mind relationship...includes the problem of man's position in the physical world...'World 1'. The world of conscious human processes I shall call 'World 2', and the world of the objective creations of the human mind I shall call 'World 3'. |edition=A lecture given in Mannheim, 8 May, 1972}} See also {{cite web |title=Three Worlds: The Tanner Lecture on Human Values |date=April 7, 1978 |author=Karl Popper |url=http://tannerlectures.utah.edu/_documents/a-to-z/p/popper80.pdf |publisher=Tanner Humanities Center, The University of Utah |accessdate=June 1, 2015}} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Ratner> | |||
Ratner continues: "The mind-body problem of how the physical body/brain produces mental, subjective qualia, is the wrong way to frame the origin of consciousness." See: {{cite book |title=Macro Cultural Psychology: A Political Philosophy of Mind |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=2ZBoAgAAQBAJ&pg=PA96 |pages=p. 96 |author=Carl Ratner |isbn=0199706298 |year=2011 |publisher=Oxford University Press}} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name= Rosenbaum> | |||
A brief discussion of possible interpretation of these results is found in {{cite book |title=Human Motor Control |pages=p. 86 |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=MsFmds_ACBwC&pg=PA86&lpg=PA86 |isbn=0123742269 |year=2009 |edition=2nd ed |publisher=Academic Press |author=David A. Rosenbaum}} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Rogers> | |||
{{cite book |author=Alec Rogers |title=Cognitive Set Theory |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=qkEqfI3H4zkC&pg=PA85 |page=85 |chapter=The division between subjective and objective defines life |isbn=0983037604 |year=2012 |publisher=ArborRhythms}} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Schrodinger> | |||
"Every man's world picture is and always remains a construct of the mind and cannot be proved to have any other existence, yet the conscious mind itself remains a stranger within that construct, it has no living space in it, you can spot it nowhere in space...We have entirely taken to thinking of the personality of a human being...as located in the interior of its body. To learn that it cannot really be found there is so amazing that it meets with doubt and hesitation, we are very loath to admit it." And later (p. 123) "It is very difficult for us to take stock of the fact that the localization of the personality, of the conscious mind, inside the body is only symbolic, just an aid for practical use." Reprinted in {{cite book |title=What is Life?: With Mind and Matter and Autobiographical Sketches |author=Erwin Schrödinger |chapter=Mind and Matter |pages=p. 122 |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=hP9-WIEyv8cC&pg=PA122 |isbn=1107604664 |year=2012 |publisher=Cambridge University Press |editor=Forward by Roger Penrose }} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Schweber> | |||
{{cite book |author=Silvan S. Schweber |year=1994 |title= QED and the men who made it: Dyson, Feynman, Schwinger, and Tomonaga |publisher=Princeton University Press |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=61n5dE7FJQgC&pg=PA465 |page=p. 465 |isbn=0691033277}} A more technical description is provided by {{cite book |author=Adrian Wüthrich |year=2010 |title=The Genesis of Feynman Diagrams |publisher=Springer |page=p. 9 |isbn=9048192277 |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=-y7hxVHO7xMC&pg=PA9}} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Shapiro> | |||
{{cite book |title=Fad Surfing in the Boardroom: Managing in the Age of Instant Answers |chapter=The high stakes thrill of fad surfing in the boardroom |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=tY3v5-6kL6cC&pg=PR13 |page=''xiii'' |author= Eileen C. Shapiro |isbn=0201441950 |year=1996 |publisher=Basic Books}} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Silverman> | |||
{{cite book |chapter=Locating places |author=Irwin Silverman, Jean Choi |title=The Handbook of Evolutionary Psychology |editor=David M Buss, ed |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=esDW3xTKoLIC&pg=PA180&lpg=PA180 |pages=p. 180 |isbn=0471264032 |year=2006 |publisher=John Wiley & Sons}} | |||
</ref> | </ref> | ||
<ref name=Skinner> | <ref name=Skinner> | ||
{{cite book |title=About Behaviorism |author=BF Skinner |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=K7WKkwPzNqsC&printsec=frontcover |isbn=0307797848 |year=2011 |publisher=Random House Digital, Inc}} | {{cite book |title=About Behaviorism |author=BF Skinner |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=K7WKkwPzNqsC&printsec=frontcover |isbn=0307797848 |year=2011 |publisher=Random House Digital, Inc}} | ||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Spinoza> | |||
{{cite book |author= Benedict de Spinoza |year=2008 |chapter= Part III: On the origin and nature of the emotions; Postulates (Proposition II, Note) |editor= R. H. M. Elwes, trans |title=The Ethics |publisher=Digireads.com Publishing |edition =Original work published 1677 |isbn=1420931148 |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=2tTweH2JeXsC&pg=PA54&lpg=PA54 |pages=p. 54}} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Stanovitch> | |||
{{cite book |title=The Robot's Rebellion: Finding Meaning in the Age of Darwin |author=Keith E. Stanovich |isbn=0226771253 |publisher=University of Chicago Press |year=2005 |url=https://www.google.com/search?tbo=p&tbm=bks&q=%22We+can+use+these+higher-order+concepts+to+critique+the+nature+of+our+own+first-order+desires%22&num=10}} See in particular Chapter 8: ''A soul without mystery'', pp. 207 ''ff''. | |||
</ref> | </ref> | ||
Line 199: | Line 653: | ||
</ref> | </ref> | ||
<ref name= | <ref name=stoic> | ||
{{cite book |title=The | {{cite book |title=The Stoics on Determinism and Compatibilism |author=Ricardo Salles |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=dk0XeajvTLAC&printsec=frontcover |isbn=0754639762 |publisher=Ashgate Publishing |year=2005}} | ||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Strawson> | |||
{{cite book |title=Freedom and belief |author=Galen Strawson |pages=p. 6 |isbn=0199247501 |edition=Revised ed |year=2010 |publisher=Oxford University Press |url=http://www.amazon.com/Freedom-Belief-Galen-Strawson/dp/0199247501/ref=sr_1_1?s=books&ie=UTF8&qid=1347204067&sr=1-1&keywords=0199247501#reader_0199247501 }} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Strawson2> | |||
{{cite web |author=Galen Strawson |date=April 19, 2011 |title= Free will |editor=E. Craig, ed |work=Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy |accessdate=December 09, 2013 |url=http://www.rep.routledge.com/article/V014}} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Strother> | |||
{{cite journal |title=The conscious experience of action and intention |author=Lars Strother, Sukhvinder Singh Obhi |journal=Exp Brain Res |volume=198 |year=2009 |pages=535-539 |doi= 10.1007/s00221-009-1946-7 |url=http://publish.uwo.ca/~lstroth/StrotherObhi_EBR_2009.pdf}} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Swartz> | |||
{{cite book |title=Culture and Power: The Sociology of Pierre Bourdieu |chapter=The subjective/objective antimony |author=David Swartz |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=wtv6upysjjgC&pg=PA55 |page=55 |isbn=0226785955 |year=1998 |edition=2nd |publisher=University of Chicago Press}} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Tooby> | |||
{{cite book |chapter=Conceptual foundations of evolutionary psychology |author=John Tooby, Leda Cosmides |title=The Handbook of Evolutionary Psychology |editor=David M Buss, ed |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=esDW3xTKoLIC&pg=PA54&lpg=PA54 |pages=pp. 53-54 |isbn=0471264032 |year=2006 |publisher=John Wiley & Sons}} | |||
</ref> | </ref> | ||
<ref name= | <ref name=Volkow> | ||
{{cite book |title=The | {{cite book |title=Science In Medicine: The JCI Textbook Of Molecular Medicine |chapter=The addicted human brain: insights from imaging studies |author= Nora D Volkow, Joanna S Fowler, and Gene-Jack Wang |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=Ykvt1S9n8V0C&pg=PA1061 |pages=pp. 1061 ''ff'' |isbn=0763750832 |year=2007 |publisher=Jones & Bartlett Learning |editor= Andrew R Marks and Ushma S Neill, eds}} | ||
</ref> | </ref> | ||
Line 218: | Line 692: | ||
{{cite book |title=The Cambridge Handbook of Consciousness |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=o9ZRc6-FDg8C&pg=PA117&lpg=PA117 |chapter=Chapter 6: Artificial intelligence and consciousness |author=Drew McDermott |pages=pp. 117 ''ff'' |editor=Philip David Zelazo, Morris Moscovitch, Evan Thompson, eds |isbn=0521857430 |year=2007 |publisher=Cambridge University Press}} | {{cite book |title=The Cambridge Handbook of Consciousness |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=o9ZRc6-FDg8C&pg=PA117&lpg=PA117 |chapter=Chapter 6: Artificial intelligence and consciousness |author=Drew McDermott |pages=pp. 117 ''ff'' |editor=Philip David Zelazo, Morris Moscovitch, Evan Thompson, eds |isbn=0521857430 |year=2007 |publisher=Cambridge University Press}} | ||
</ref> | </ref> | ||
}} | }}[[Category:Suggestion Bot Tag]] |
Latest revision as of 16:01, 18 August 2024
Free will refers to that feeling, or experience, one has that one can have complete control to choose among alternative actions, even in the face of psychological and other conflicting influences.[1][2][3][4] As a phenomenon, 'free will' transcends any encapsulation in words, just like an eclipse of the moon is a phenomenon that can be addressed by devouring dragons or by planetary motions, but still is an eclipse, however it is described. A difference from an eclipse, however, is that the experience of free will, despite its prevalence, is not established objectively by third-party observations, but by introspection and by reports by others of their own subjective mental life. Whether we all are deluded, or whether the matter lies outside or within the reach of science, the experience is there, and these and other wide-ranging questions about this experience are part of its exploration.[5]
It is an age-old concern to separate what we can do something about, choose to do, from what we cannot. Much of human experience is interpreted as depending upon our choices. Capturing the content of this subjective formulation, one stance regarding free will is the philosophical position that human beings are able to choose between different courses of action in any given circumstance,[6] whereas the opposite position, determinism, claims that all our mental states and actions are made necessary by preceding causes, and the idea that we are free at all is an illusion.[7]
These diametric extremes, on the one hand we always are in complete control, and on the other that we never are in control, unnecessarily restrict our options, an example of false dichotomy,[8] referred to specifically in this instance as naïve dualism.[9] Reality lies somewhere else, as it is abundantly clear that our actions can be dictated by factors outside our control and outside our awareness,[10] but it is unclear that such factors are decisive in every instance or in the long run. The present situation is that the ability to exercise free will is known definitely to be limited by many factors, sometimes strongly limited. An alternative to the "either-or" formulation is metaphysical libertarianism, which simply asserts that determinism is false, and at least sometimes humans exert control over their choices.[11] However, a useful discussion of free will may require vocabulary and concepts not yet developed, and whatever its ultimate formulation, a persuasive account of free will requires an extrapolation of the present understanding of the brain and the mind beyond what is verifiable today.[12][13]
The controllable and uncontrollable aspects of decision making are logically separable using the following device:
|
The connection between will and action thereby is separated for further discussion. In particular, is there in nature anything that actually inhabits the domain of "will" so-defined, a domain beyond the reach of "external constraints"? A related distinction is that between brain and mind, with brain the physical matter where mental processes take place, and mind somehow (unclearly) related to consciousness and will. |
All of us have subjectively experienced being torn between doing one thing or another –what we would like to do, what we think we should do, or what we think others would appreciate our doing, and so on. We might assume that the decision is up to us, that we are free to do one thing or another, and others may heap blame or praise on us assuming the same thing. This assumption is what is meant by free will –the intuition that whatever we may have done in actual fact, could have been otherwise because we might have decided on another course of action, and that before taking the action we were free to choose between alternatives. The claim might be: "Consciousness has the ability to override its genetic (and other) instructions and to set its own independent course of action."[15]
At the same time, we realize that some aspects of the world work in ways that can be understood because there are law-like processes that can be deciphered, and that allow us to predict some future events based upon observations of past events. The principle operating here is that future events are governed by physical laws rooted in past events, and the notion that this kind of explanation applies to everything that happens is known as determinism. Some have argued that the probabilistic nature of quantum mechanics opens a door to a randomness in human behavior, which is foreign to human experience. Inasmuch as random atomic events are not under our control any more than predetermined events, determinism can be rewritten to include this randomness, for example, as follows: All our decisions are either implied by past events, or by random events, that in both cases do not involve us as agents, but which we simply witness.[11]
If the world is deterministic, our feeling that we are free to choose an action is simply an illusion. We have trouble believing all our actions are beyond our control, and that our sense of freedom is totally illusory, but we also have problems thinking that our actions are totally within our control. Although it is an exaggeration (at least at the moment) to think that science requires determinism,[16] it is apparent that "consciousness plays a far smaller role in human life than Western culture has tended to believe."[17][18]
This dilemma is what in philosophy is known as the problem of free will (or sometimes referred to by its flip-side as the dilemma of determinism), and it is a dilemma because it is difficult to decide how to assign moral responsibility for our actions. In a more nuanced formulation, the dilemma stems from the question posed as follows:
"Are behaviors, judgments, and other higher mental processes the product of free conscious choices, as influenced by internal psychological states (motives, preferences, etc.), or are those higher mental processes determined by those states?" John A. Bargh, Free Will is Un-natural[19] |
A clear statement of the dilemma is as follows:
"The idea of free will, though now rather in disfavor, expressed the popular and philosophical view that behavior reflects the outcome of a struggle between an autonomous, relatively virtuous, possibly spiritual self and the baser forces of external demand and inner cravings. The assumption that two different processes battle it out to determine action has been fundamental in theological views, such as beliefs about the judgment of individual souls based upon whether they choose virtuous or sinful acts. Likewise, it is central to some modern legal judgments that assign punishment not just on the basis of the action and its (criminal) consequences but also on the supposed state of mind of the perpetrator – reserving lesser punishment for crimes committed in mental states...that supposedly reduce the capacity of the nobler part of the self to restrain the wickeder impulses..." Roy F Baumeister et al., Free Willpower: A limited resource theory of volition, choice and self-regulation[20] |
Mind-body problem
The idea of free will is one aspect of the mind-body problem, that is, consideration of the relation between mind (for example, consciousness, memory and judgment) and body (for example, the human brain and nervous system). The 'mind' may not be coterminous with the brain, as Schrödinger has suggested,[22] and cultural psychology suggests that "Culture produces the mind; brain circuitry does not."[23] Enactivists take the view that the brain, the mind, the environment, form a tightly coupled system that, at least in some aspects, defies separation into individual quasi-autonomous pieces.[24]
In the context of free will, does the relation between mind and body allow for the mind to 'cause' neurological states, or is the mind simply an artifact or correlate of what the brain and nervous system are doing on their own? That question is presented as though the issue is empirical, but there are serious questions as to whether it is properly phrased that way, and whether standard methods separating the observed from the observer really apply to this investigation. Are there causal connections behind known correlations between subjective mental activity and objectively identified neurological events? Is the language of 'cause' and 'effect' too limited to describe huge systems of sensors with complex feedback arrangements? The discussion of free will falls into various parts: some empirical (What is going on in the brain?), some semantic (What are the possible meanings of free will, and are new concepts necessary?), some theoretical (there are many of these, among them: Does the disturbance of what is observed by the very act of observation imply that terms like free will and the terms used in neuroscience are fundamentally incompatible descriptions, making psychology irreducible to neuroscience?).
For example, interactionalist dualism suggests that some physical events cause some mental acts and some mental acts cause some physical events. Dualism allows humans free will, because mind only is correlated with brain activity, and is not reducible to it.[25] A modern dualist position from the field of artificial intelligence, or AI, is made by so called strong AI theorists, who say that the mind is separate from the brain in the same way that a computer algorithm exists independent of its many possible realizations in coding and physical implementation, and the brain and its 'wiring' is analogous to a computer and its software.[26] (Perhaps it is worth pointing out that the brain and its operation is known to be quite different from any man-made computer.[27]) Another version is the "three world" formulation of Popper.[28] These are examples of what is called epistemological pluralism, that is the notion that the mind-body problem is not reducible to the concepts of the natural sciences.
One contrasting approach is called cognitive naturalism, in which mind is simply part of nature, perhaps merely a feature of most very complex self-programming feedback systems, and must be studied by the methods of empirical science.[25] Certainly, some areas of the brain (see image) are connected to aspects of mental function and consciousness.
Attempts are being made to soften the boundary between these two views based upon self-organizing systems, exploring the conjecture that such systems can have a causal power over the organization of their deterministic subsystems, expressed in the ways these substratum elements are organized and put into action.[29]
“What must be explained is how a self-organizing or dynamical system can have a causal power over its own substrata, which is not reducible to the sum of the actions of the substrata, while at the same time causal closure is not violated at the substratum level.[...] any such causal analysis must use a theory of self-organization as their starting point, since only a dynamical system promises [...] the power to appropriate substratum elements into its own basins of attraction, rather than letting those basins be merely a higher-level description of the independent actions of the substrata.” R. D. Ellis Part III. The mind-body problem[29], p.49. |
One aspect of this development is to explore the question: Is a machine realizable for which the goals of the machine are not imposed from the outside, but produced by the machine itself?[30]
An outstanding unsolved issue in the mind-body problem often is called the hard problem of consciousness, how physical phenomena acquire subjective characteristics becoming, for example, colors and tastes.[31] For example, "it is possible to know all the physical and functional facts concerning the operation of human brains without, for example, knowing what it is like subjectively to experience vertigo."[32] The subjective intuition of free will may fall into this category as well.
Philosophical positions
The discussion of free will sprang historically from attempts to reconcile the sense that the mind could freely make decisions that affected a person's future with the observation that at least some things in nature were simply the consequences of other things. A more modern view of free will concerns the relation between the subjective, free will, color, taste, and the objective or scientific mode of observation. Both are outlined below.
Compatibilist-incompatibilist arguments
Using T, F for "true" and "false" and ? for undecided, there are exactly nine positions regarding determinism/free will that consist of any two of these three possibilities:[33]
1 | 2 | 3 | 4 | 5 | 6 | 7 | 8 | 9 | |
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Determinism D | T | F | T | F | T | F | ? | ? | ? |
Free will FW | F | T | T | F | ? | ? | F | T | ? |
Incompatibilism may occupy any of the nine positions except (5), (8) or (3), which last corresponds to soft determinism. Position (1) is hard determinism,and position (2) is libertarianism. The position (1) of hard determinism adds to the table the contention that D implies FW is untrue, and the position (2) of libertarianism adds the contention that FW implies D is untrue. Position (9) may be called hard incompatibilism if one interprets ? as meaning both concepts are of dubious value. Compatibilism itself may occupy any of the nine positions, that is, there is no logical contradiction between determinism and free will, and either or both may be true or false in principle. Below some of these positions are examined in more detail.[33][34]
Incompatibilism
“Experience teaches us no less clearly than reason, that men believe themselves to be free, simply because they are conscious of their actions, and unconscious of the causes whereby those actions are determined.” B de Spinoza Ethics[35] |
One approach, of course, is simply to accept as a fact that human beings are not free, a position termed hard determinism or incompatibilism.[11] To accept this position is to accept that our actions are caused by things other than our will –that actions do not originate in volition (willing), but rather in forces that determine its disposition in one way or another, a view often associated with stoicism.[36] Hard determinism, however, insofar as it accepts a causal chain of events, means our present actions are determined in the past, and some consider that view to wholly destroy any notion of moral responsibility. From this stance, freedom is considered a necessary component of responsibility, for why should anyone be blamed or praised for actions that could not have been otherwise?
Stoics, however, considered that an agent was responsible for thinking through their choices, even though the appearance of choice is illusory.[36] This curious situation led to much debate over the centuries, with Chrysippus (279 – 206 BC) attempting a way out of this apparent contradiction by separating external antecedent causes from the internal disposition receiving this cause, similar temptations affect those of different character differently, a solution adopted by many thinkers since that time in various formulations.[37]
Classically, the idea of determinism goes back at least as far as Laplace, who posited (based upon Newton's laws of mechanics) that an omniscient observer knowing with infinite precision all the positions and velocities of every particle in the universe could predict the future entirely. Needless to say, omniscient observers are imaginary creations.[38] A less restrictive view of determinism than that of Laplace is discussed by Nagel.[39] "A theory is deterministic if, and only if, given its state variables for some initial period, the theory logically determines a unique set of values for those variables for any other period." To extend this idea to a view of determinism, in addition one would have to assert that the Universe is governed, at least in principle, by some amalgam of deterministic theories. Nagel argues that a deterministic formulation does not require the viability of omniscient observers, but only the possibility in principle of determinism: "A theory is labeled properly as a deterministic one if analysis of its internal structure shows that the theoretical state of a system at one instant logically determines a unique state of that system for another instant." The use of the term "state" incorporates field theories like the Standard Model within determinism.
Libertarianism
Others have argued that determinism is false, or that at the very least, human actions are a special case and stand outside the requirements of a deterministic universe.[11] In simple terms, freedom of thought is distinguished from freedom of action, and their connection is made a subject of study. By separating the rules of thought, one might be free to choose between alternatives, one might have causal powers.
Saint Augustine held this view, the capacity for metaphysical freedom.[40] Kant also subscribed to this view: besides nature and empirical knowledge, there is the realm of things in themselves accessible to thought and governed by different rules; a distinction between phenomena and noumena.[41]
There are other ways to suggest that "reality" is larger than the realm where determinism applies. For example, Pierre Duhem suggested that scientific theory was simply a device to facilitate economy of thought, and could not be considered to encompass "reality".[42] Thus, thought is a distillation of reality, and what goes on "in reality" is a much deeper and broader question than how we describe it. Similar to consciousness itself, scientific theory is a synopsis of some of what goes on, not the full text. This view of science as dealing with only part of the picture opens the way to more modern statements of the separation of causality in nature from that in the mind.
Another way to limit the applicability of determinism is to introduce the role of subjectivity, more generally, consciousness, as a matter beyond the reach of the methods of science and its requirement for public verifiability. So, for example, pain is a subjective phenomenon. It can sometimes be correlated to verifiable events in the nervous system, but the experience of pain is inaccessible except through subjective reports from the victim. The so-far unobtainable goal of relating subjective experiences like pain, color, taste to verifiable constructs is called the hard problem of consciousness,[43] and the experience of free will falls under this label. An additional issue related to this separation of the subjective and the objective is the question of mental causation,[44] the ability (or not) of the mind to affect the material world. This concern may have more respectable goals than establishing telekinesis.
For example, we have this modern statement of the claim for mental causation:
"The nonconcious forms of self-regulation may follow different causal principles and do not rely on the same resources as the conscious and effortful ones." Roy F Baumeister et al., Free Willpower: A limited resource theory of volition, choice and self-regulation[20] |
A different approach questions the concept of "causality" itself, considering it a construct inappropriate to the description of human and animal behavior. See the section below on causality.
Compatibilism
An intermediate view has been to soften the requirements of what it means to be free. One accepts the fact that actions have causes, but argues that this does not mean we are not free.[11]
In the approach known as soft determinism, I am still free even though my character, common sense and so forth, strongly support a course of action, because they do not compel me to act in this way, nor preclude alternatives. Of course freedom understood in this way is not an arbitrary freedom. It is freedom in the sense that nothing stops me from doing otherwise, even though it is unlikely. Put in an extreme form: "A puppet is free as long as he loves his strings".[45]
What are the "strings" attached to our decisions? The questions of character, predisposition, programming and so on, are part of the field of behaviorism, where behavior modification, reinforcement, and so forth are studied.[46] A closely related field is cognitive psychology, the psychology of cognition, studying matters such as the processes involved in memorization and decision making.[47][48]
Subjective-objective dichotomy
An undecided question is whether the world of science and the universe are coextensive. Science has practical impact upon technology and our understanding of interconnections. However, there are areas where science so far has had little impact. So there exists a difference in optimism about science, with one view opining that science will gradually extend to everything, and the opposite view opining that won't happen. For example, the statement is found in many books:
"...consciousness is a biological process that will eventually be explained in terms of molecular signaling pathways used by interacting populations of nerve cells.." –Eric R. Kandel, In Search of Memory: The Emergence of a New Science of Mind - [49] |
On the other hand, the contrary view is described below in the section on complementarity.[50][51]
Free will is an arena in which to contrast these viewpoints. Free will is a widely shared intuition.[52] Like other aspects of consciousness, it appears to escape inclusion in a scientific explanation, and one has to ask whether science can say anything useful about this intuition. Free will stands at the nexus between subjective and objective realities, and is possibly the most interesting situation where these two meet.
Free will often is contrasted with determinism. In considering a statement involving determinism, like All events p are determined by other events P , in order to be consistent with science today, and avoid oversimplification, one has to be very clear about how the events (p,P) are defined. One also has to replace "determined" by something like "logically imply".
"a theory is deterministic if, and only if, given its state variables for some initial period, the theory logically determines a unique set of values for those variables for any other period." –Ernest Nagel, Alternative descriptions of physical state [53] |
The need for great care in defining "events" and "determined" results in detailed descriptions of what constitutes an "event" and how one is said to "determine" another, and raises questions of how to relate the "universe" to these detailed descriptions.
These developments take the subjective-objective distinction to a more general level than simply arguments over the prospects of success of extending science into certain areas of experience. A Popper-like view emerges with an "event" as some kind of formalized "state" and the relationship "determines" phrased as a "logical implication" of connection between states, all combined as parts of one or another abstract theory. That formalization puts a lot of emphasis upon mental constructions. From the stance of a Duhem, or a Popper, or a Hawking, the use of an intermediary, elaborate mental construction is a meld of the subjective and objective. It is used to determine connections about objective events, but the form of the theoretical construct is a product of subjective activities, and its particular form may well be more about the brain than anything else. Much like a computer algorithm can be expressed as assembly language instructions peculiar to a particular computer by translating the algorithm into steps that particular computer can handle, some aspects of the universe's operation can be expressed in terms of mental constructs.
Lest this apparatus be thought of as an entirely formal understanding, some among us actually do have intuitive grasp of these abstractions, perhaps analogous to the fact that some among us hear music in the sounds around them. Quoting Feynman about his creative process:
"It is impossible to differentiate the symbols from the thing; but it is very visual. It is hard to believe it, but I see these things not as mathematical expressions but a mixture of a mathematical expression wrapped into and around, in a vague way, around the object. So I see all the time visual things associated with what I am trying to do." –Richard P. Feyman, as quoted by Schweber: QED and the men who made it: Dyson, Feynman, Schwinger, and Tomonaga[54] |
This comment could be paralleled by others about the intuitions of musicians and mathematicians.[55] The point is that the creation of scientific theories is subjective, and the very concepts of determinism are themselves subjective and mutable creations of the human mind. What is in charge here: the intuition conceiving the theory, or the theory that results; or is it an unending back-and-forth spiral from one to the other? Using such theory to assess mental activity itself, including free will, is something of a bootstrapping process that might never converge. The question of whether an intuitive free will submits to a critique by some deterministic theory has aspects of an infinite regress. Did a rat "decide" to run a maze, or was it "instinct"? Did the biologist in the laboratory "decide" to build the maze, or was it the zeitgeist of the field? Did the corporation "decide" to build the laboratory, or was it a fad?[56]
"When stated at a general level, the subjective/objective dichotomy is recognized by most social scientists as one of the enduring metatheoretical dilemmas in the social sciences..." –David Swartz: Culture and Power: The Sociology of Pierre Bourdieu, p. 55[57] |
"It is not possible to resolve which of the subjective or physical universes ultimately contains the other." –Alec Rogers: Cognitive Set Theory, p.85[58] |
Complementarity
In quantum mechanics the notion of complementarity arises, that is, different aspects of a description that are mutually exclusive. Bohr (1922 winner of the Nobel Prize in physics) suggested complementarity is useful outside of quantum theory. In asking whether one can perform an action, one is both observer and subject, which is posited to be an untenable situation: one must adopt one or the other stance.[59][60] To quote Niels Bohr:[51]
"For instance, it is impossible, from our standpoint, to attach an unambiguous meaning to the view sometimes expressed that the probability of the occurrence of certain atomic processes in the body might be under the direct influence of the will. In fact, according to the generalized interpretation of the psycho-physical parallelism, the freedom of the will is to be considered as a feature of conscious life which corresponds to functions of the organism that not only evade a causal mechanical description but resist even a physical analysis carried to the extent required for an unambiguous application of the statistical laws of atomic mechanics. Without entering into metaphysical speculations, I may perhaps add that an analysis of the very concept of explanation would, naturally, begin and end with a renunciation as to explaining our own conscious activity."... |
"...On the contrary, the recognition of the limitation of mechanical concepts in atomic physics would rather seem suited to conciliate the apparently contrasting viewpoints of physiology and psychology. Indeed, the necessity of considering the interaction between the measuring instruments and the object under investigation in atomic mechanics exhibits a close analogy to the peculiar difficulties in psychological analysis arising from the fact that the mental content is invariably altered when the attention is concentrated on any special feature of it." |
These observations are echoed by experimentalists studying brain function:[61]
"...it is important to be clear about exactly what experience one wants one's subjects to introspect. Of course, explaining to subjects exactly what the experimenter wants them to experience can bring its own problems–...instructions to attend to a particular internally generated experience can easily alter both the timing and he content of that experience and even whether or not it is consciously experienced at all." Susan Pockett, The neuroscience of movement[61] |
Another description of this issue is by Northoff:[50]
"Epistemically, the mind is determined by mental states, which are accessible in First-Person Perspective. In contrast, the brain, as characterized by neuronal states, can be accessed in Third-Person Perspective. The Third-Person Perspective focuses on other persons and thus on the neuronal states of others' brain while excluding the own brain. In contrast, the First-Person Perspective could potentially provide epistemic access to own brain...However, the First-Person Perspective provides access only to the own mental states but not to the own brain and its neuronal states." Georg Northoff, Philosophy of the Brain: The Brain Problem, p. 5[50] |
These observations suggest the possibility that "free will" and neurology inhabit different realms, and it is confusion to try to explain "free will" using a neurological approach that by its very nature excludes the effects of observation upon what is observed. In broad terms, this argument complements that of Chrysippus (279 – 206 BC).[37]
Causality
In extending the application of the principle of complementarity, Bohr questioned the everyday ideas of causality:
"...any observation necessitates an interference with the course of the phenomena, which is of such a nature that it deprives us of the foundation underlying the causal mode of description." Neils Bohr: The Atomic Theory and the Fundamental Principles underlying the Description of Nature[62] |
Bohr considered these reservations might apply in trying to explain the connection between mental and physical events in terms of observation altering what is observed. If our notion of causality is questioned, "free will" as mental causation takes on a different interpretation.
Similar reservations have been expressed by others, but take a broader, more historical approach. Historically, two types of causality (the "being responsible for something else") are distinguished, with several sub-genres.[63] The first kind of causes is that which is included in the effect and is part of it (embedment); the arising of something out of itself. The second kind of causes does not reside in the effect and is separate from it.
In the first category, two subdivisions arise:
- causa materialis or material cause: the implied but not yet realized result, as Michelangelo said his act of sculpture "released" the form already present and buried within the marble.[64]
- causa formalis or formal causality: a mental construct created to relate an effect to a cause.
The second category of external causes also divides into two:
- causa efficiencs or efficient causality: cause and effect can be separated and determined, the usual 'cause' of science as stimulus and response.
- causa finalis or final causality: the objective as shaping the action; as may entail its expression though no cause as yet exists. Thus, the desire for a king may cause a coronation, and goals set by evolution may determine a response.
These notions of cause may not be all that distinct. For example, the "principle of least action", and its extension to the Feynman path integral, predicts the realized path of a system as a minimization of 'action' over all possible paths, seemingly suggesting that the system 'action' (a causa materialis) already embodies the path to be taken given the objective of 'least action' (a causa finalis). And yet this formulation is equivalent to those based upon Newton's laws or quantum mechanics, which invoke only causa efficiencs, and it has been argued that physics theories themselves constitute a causa formalis, no more than a mental shorthand to link selected events, a subset of all events.[42]
Northoff regards the restriction of cause to causa efficiencs precludes a proper understanding of the dynamics and self-organization of the brain, restricting explanations to an 'outside of the brain' point of view: “the possibility of mental causation is necessarily dependent on the possibility of 'final and formal causality'”.[65]
Along these lines, Freeman introduces the replacement of "causality" by what he calls "circular causality" to "allow for the contribution of self-organizing dynamics", the "formation of macroscopic population dynamics that shapes the patterns of activity of the contributing individuals", applicable to "interactions between neurons and neural masses...and between the behaving animal and its environment":
"Circular causality departs so strongly from the classical tenets of necessity, invariance, and precise temporal order that the only reason to call it that is to satisfy the human habitual need for causes....The very strong appeal of agency to explain events may come from the subjective experience of cause and effect that develops early in human life, before the acquisition of language...the question I raise here is whether brains share this property with other material objects in the world. " (Walter J. Freeman, Consciousness, intentionality and causality[66]) |
Freeman's usage for the term circular causality appears akin to the views of Kelso,[67] and is more radical than the common use of this term, which refers to causality in a system with feedback.[68] A more specific use of this term is as follows:
"Note we are dealing here with circular causality. On the one hand the order parameter enslaves the atoms, but on the other hand it is itself generated by the joint action of the atoms" (Hermann Haken, Information and Self-Organization: A Macroscopic Approach to Complex Systems[69]) |
Self-programming robots
Today robots can be made that adapt their responses to their environment through self-programming, so-called intelligent robots. Much of the description of these machines seems parallel to human behavior, although technology has still not reached sufficient complexity to make a strong case for the similarities.[70]
"Some people think that consciousness can arise only in organic, of flesh-and-blood beings. Others speculate that self-awareness might develop in any sufficiently complex network that is set up to operate like a brain...Could a conscious robot – a being created by humans and not by God – ever be said to have a soul? "[71] |
Is such a machine deterministic? We cannot predict the machine's exact behavior without a complete knowledge of its personal history with its environment, the reliability of its components, and its present state of programming, uncertainties in which limit us to probabilistic statements. It may be that this question is objectively undecidable, and has only an answer according to some or another theoretical formulation, in particular, a statistical answer indicating a probable range of responses to a probable range of inputs.
Groups of cooperating robots also are envisioned:
"The interaction of multiple behavioral robots can be regarded as a continuum between two diverse types of behavior. At one extreme, the behavior can regarded as being egoistic, where a robot is concerned purely with self directed behavior, e.g. energy conservation. At the other extreme their behavior can be regarded as being altruistic, e.g. when a group of robots need to work together to perform some common task."[72] |
One can conjecture that some such groups could evolve following a Darwinian scheme, not only an interest of engineers,[73] but a recurrent topic of science fiction.[74]
"The marvels accomplished by evolution inspired many researchers with the long term goal of automatically designing and even manufacturing complete robotics "lifeforms" with as little human intervention as possible." (Doncieux et al., §1.4.4 p. 12[73]) |
Implementation of decisions
Decision theory describes the processes, constraints, and determinants of human decision making.[75][76] In connection with free will, an important aspect of these studies is autonomy, the ability of individuals "to determine the direction of their lives in accordance with their beliefs, principles and values".[77] Brain studies have provided some insight into the brain functions involved in decisions and their implementation.
Addiction
The separation of freedom of action from freedom of will is demonstrated in addiction. An unwilling addict has identified withdrawal as desirable but finds themselves unable to enforce that action.[78] Brain imaging of addicts and non-addicts show differences in brain activity and can relate the process of addiction to a reprogramming of the brain's handling of dopamine that can be reversed only with a very prolonged and multipronged therapy.[79]
"Most PET (Positron Emission Tomography) studies of drug addiction have concentrated on the brain dopamine (DA) system, since this is considered to be the neurotransmitter system through which most drugs of abuse exert their reinforcing effects. A reinforcer is operationally defined as an event that increases the probability of a subsequent response, and drugs of abuse are considered to be much stronger reinforcers than natural reinforcers (e.g. sex and food). The brain DA system also regulates motivation and drive for everyday activities. These imaging studies have revealed that acute and chronic drug consumption have different effects on proteins involved involved in DA synaptic transmission. ... chronic drug consumption results in marked decrease in DA activity which persists months after detoxification and which is associated with deregulation of frontal brain regions. " (Volkow et al.[80]) |
"One of the most consistent findings from imaging studies is that of abnormalities in the prefrontal cortex... The prefrontal cortex is involved in decision making and in inhibitory control... Thus its disruption could lead to inadequate decisions that favor immediate rewards over delayed but more favorable responses. It could also account for the impaired control over the intake of the drug even when the addicted subject expresses the desire to refrain from taking the drug. " (Volkow et al.[80]) |
Response times
Studies of the timing between actions and the conscious decision to act have a bearing upon free will. A subject's declaration of intention to move a finger appears after the brain has begun to implement the action, suggesting to some that unconsciously the brain has made the decision before the conscious mental act to do so. Some believe the implication is that free will was not involved in the decision and is an illusion. The first of these experiments reported the brain registered activity related to the move about 0.2 s before movement onset.[81] However, these authors also found that awareness of action was anticipatory to activity in the muscle underlying the movement; the entire process resulting in action involves more steps than just the onset of brain activity.[82][83]
Some argue that placing the question of free will in the context of motor control is too narrow. The objection is that the time scales involved in motor control are very short, and motor control involves a great deal of unconscious action, with much physical movement entirely unconscious and not a matter of intention at all. On that basis "...free will cannot be squeezed into time frames of 150-350 ms; free will is a longer term phenomenon" and free will is a higher level activity that "cannot be captured in a description of neural activity or of muscle activation..." [84]
The bearing of timing results upon notions of free will appears complex, and remains a topic of discussion.
Emotion
From the perspective of evolutionary psychology, emotions evolved in humans in response to environmental challenges, and serve to organize human responses according to success in handling ancestral experience:[85]
"an emotion is a superordinate program whose function is to direct the activities and interactions of many subprograms, including those governing perception, ...categorization and conceptual frameworks,...communication processes, and the recalibration of probability estimates, situation assessments... ." "All cognitive programs [...] are sometimes mistaken for homunculi,[86] that is, entities endowed with free will. A homunculus scans the environment and freely chooses successful actions. ... It is the task of cognitive psychologists to replace theories that implicitly posit such an impossible entity with theories that can be implemented as fixed programs with open parameters." "Just as a computer can have an hierarchy of programs, some of which control the activation of others, the human mind can as well. Far from being internal free agents, these programs have an unchanging structure regardless of the needs of the individual or his or here circumstances because they were designed to create states that worked well in ancestral situations, regardless of their consequences in the present." John Tooby and Leda Cosmides: Conceptual foundations of evolutionary psychology[85] |
Other than undefined "open parameters", perhaps related to "recalibrations", these words leave little room for the effects found in behavioral psychology, cognitive psychology, and the field of developmental psychology associated with the names of Jean Piaget and Lev Vygotsky, which find much room for environmental factors arising during the development of each individual.[87] The field of evolutionary psychology is marked by some heated controversy.
Although evolutionary psychologists attempt to understand the organization of the mind and brain based upon how they arose, it is hampered by the observation that different species arose in different environments with different responses, making cross-species comparisons very difficult.[88]
Epigenetics
"Once nurture seemed clearly distinct from nature. Now it appears that our diets and lifestyles can change the expression of our genes. How? By influencing a network of chemical switches within our cells collectively known as the epigenome."[89] Various mechanisms for transference of such environmental response to the next generation are under study.[90][91] In the context of free will, these mechanisms indicate pathways at a very basic level that can change the programming even of identical twins, and even that of successive generations. Not free will, but certainly adaptivity and originality of response in populations.
Summary
The various notions of free will conflict, but involve many of the same elements. These matters have been argued for millennia, and their resolution may depend upon developing a better understanding of what actually goes on in the brain.[66]
"Although strong advances are being made in analyzing the dynamics of the limbic system and its centerpieces, the entorhinal cortex and the hippocampus, their self-organized spatial patterns, their precise intentional contents, and their mechanisms of formation in relation to intentional action are still unknown." (Walter J. Freeman, Consciousness, intentionality and causality[66]) |
In popular accounts of this subject, the same modern developments are used as new wine in old bottles. On one hand, we have K. E. Stanovitch's The Robot's Rebellion: Finding Meaning in the Age of Darwin, which advances the view that decisions are possible that transcend mere "instrumental rationality", using goals "keyed to the life interest of the vehicle" to replace unreflective "gut" instincts originating from our genetically programmed autonomous systems.[92] On the other hand we have books like Sam Harris' Free Will,[10] and D.M. Wagener's The Illusion of Conscious Will,[93] that take the view that consciousness is completely illusory, and old-fashioned determinism is completely correct.
At an individual level, perhaps we can be viewed as complex machines with built-in goals sought using algorithms for survival, which adapt to experience. The conscious monitoring of some aspects of this reprogramming may generate feelings of mental control over our individual destinies even though these feelings may be illusory. Our survival depends upon the execution of ancestral programming that includes some adaptivity, and our mental states may be analogous to a debugger watching the evolution of some code.
The occurrence of mutations introduces a random aspect. Unusual circumstances occur due to random events, provoking new responses. New types of individual arise that exhibit novel reactions even to mundane environmental factors. These novelties may permit (or even force) individuals and societies to explore new avenues. Although once a new path is initiated, evolutionary programming and natural law exert their influences, events proceed with a complexity that defies prediction.
A broader approach to free will is based upon the idea that science is a discipline with a limited field of study, and its methods have been developed to deal with a particular subject matter with particular views of what constitutes "explanation" and "valid data", views that have yet to be generalized to deal with a broader subject matter. According to Mumford, for example, the success in treating the universe as a machine has blinded us today to what was well understood in antiquity, namely, that life is more complicated than that.[94] This view is consistent with some philosophers of science, who point out that the human practice of science involves judgements and evaluations that are not scientifically based.[95] From this perspective, the notion that free will cannot exist because man is a machine, is simply myopia.
References
- ↑ "One of the strongest supports for the free choice thesis is the unmistakable intuition of virtually every human being that he is free to make the choices he does and that the deliberations leading to those choices are also free flowing." Corliss Lamont as quoted by Gregg D Caruso (2012). Free Will and Consciousness: A Determinist Account of the Illusion of Free Will. Lexington Books, p. 8. ISBN 0739171364.
- ↑ "The freedom in question is a property, real or imagined, that nearly all adult human beings...believe themselves to possess. To say that one doesn't understand what it is, is to claim to lack the most basic understanding of the society one lives in, and such a claim is not believable." from Galen Strawson (2010). Freedom and Belief. Oxford University Press, p. 2. ISBN 0199247501. Quoted by The Information Philosopher and accessible on-line in Amazon's 'look inside' feature.
- ↑ "All normal humans experience a kind of basic, on-the-ground certainty that we, our conscious selves, cause our own voluntary acts." from Susan Pockett, William P. Banks, Shaun Gallagher (2009). “Introduction”, Susan Pockett, William P. Banks, Shaun Gallagher, eds: Does Consciousness Cause Behavior?. MIT Press, p. 1. ISBN 0262512572.
- ↑ Richard Holton (2009). “First experience of freedom: choice”, Willing, Wanting, Waiting. Oxford University Press. ISBN 9780191607547. “A quick and effective way to generate a conviction in undergraduates that they have free will is to get them to choose...The undergraduates have in the first instance an experience: an experience of doing something, namely, making a choice...they could have chosen any of a number of options and hence that they are, in that respect, unmoved movers.”
- ↑ Free will. Encyclopedia Britannica (5-28-2013). “Arguments for free will are based on the subjective experience of freedom”
- ↑ Historically, "free will" has had a number of definitions, some tied to religious notions of being able to choose between "right" and "wrong". The definition here is that described as the "common notion" by evangelical thinker Gordon H. Clark (1961). Religion, reason, and revelation. Presbyterian and Reformed Pub. Co, pp. 202-203. “Free will has been defined as the ability under given circumstances, to choose either of two courses of action... Whatever motives or inclinations a man might have, or whatever inducements may be laid before him, that might seem to turn him in a given direction, he may at a moment disregard them all and do the opposite.”
- ↑ James W. Cornman, Keith Lehrer, George Sotiros Pappas (1992). “Chapter 3: The problem of freedom and determinism”, Philosophical Problems and Arguments: An Introduction. Hackett Publishing, pp. 91 ff. ISBN 9780872201248. “If determinism is true, and I perform action A, then not only is it true that nothing else could have happened, it is also true that nothing else could have happened because of conditions over which I had no control.”
- ↑ The offering of only a pair of contrary alternatives that do not exhaust the possibilities. See Sylvan Barnet, Hugo Bedau (2010). Critical Thinking, Reading, and Writing: A Brief Guide to Argument, 7th ed. Macmillan, p. 376. ISBN 0312601603.
- ↑ The term naïve dualism is used by John Monterosso, Barry Schwartz (July 27, 2012). Did your brain make you do it?. Gray Matter. New York Times. Retrieved on 2012-07-29.
- ↑ Jump up to: 10.0 10.1 Sam Harris (2012). Free Will. Simon and Schuster, p. 5. ISBN 1451683405.
- ↑ Jump up to: 11.0 11.1 11.2 11.3 11.4 Mark Balaguer (2009). “Introduction”, Free Will As an Open Scientific Problem. MIT Press, pp. 1 ff. ISBN 0262013541.
- ↑ Thomas Nagel (1989). “Freedom”, The View From Nowhere. Oxford University Press. ISBN 9780195056440. “Nothing that might be a solution has yet been described. This is not a case where there are several possible candidate solutions and we don't know which is correct. It is a case where nothing believable has (to my knowledge) been proposed.”
- ↑ One author's view is found in: Thomas Nagel (2012). Mind and Cosmos: Why the Materialist Neo-Darwinian Conception of Nature Is Almost Certainly False. Oxford University Press. ISBN 9780199977192. “I believe that it [my capacity to respond] involves a conscious control of action that cannot be analyzed as physical causation with an epiphenomenal conscious accompaniment, and that it includes some form of free will —”
- ↑ O'Connor, Timothy (Oct 29, 2010). Edward N. Zalta, ed:Free Will. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2011 Edition).
- ↑ A paraphrase of a statement by Mihaly Csikszentmihalyi (1990). Flow: The psychology of optimal experience. Harper & Row, p. 24. ISBN 0060920432. “Consciousness has developed the ability to override its genetic instructions and to set its own independent course of action”
- ↑ The view of scientific determinism goes back to Laplace: "We ought to regard the present state of the universe as the effect of its antecedent state". However, the necessary underlying assumption of complete knowledge by an observer, including exact knowledge of the observer themselves, is an extreme idealization that renders any such claim unverifiable. See John T Roberts (2006). “Determinism”, Sahotra Sarkar, Jessica Pfeifer, Justin Garson, eds: The Philosophy of Science: An Encyclopedia. N-Z, Indeks, Volume 1. Psychology Press, pp. 197 ff. ISBN 0415939275.
- ↑ Quote from Tor Nørretranders (1998). “Preface”, The user illusion: Cutting consciousness down to size, Jonathan Sydenham translation of Maerk verden 1991 ed. Penguin Books, p. ix. ISBN 9780140230123.
- ↑ Morality and the brain; an interview with neuroscientist David Eagleman by David Edmonds and Nigel Warburton: David Eagleman (May 22, 2011). Morality and the brain. Published by philosophy bites, and the Institute of Philosophy. Retrieved on February, 2014. "It turns out that if free will exists, it's really a bit player in what's going on in the brain." (@ 4:44 minutes)
- ↑ John A Bargh (2007-011-16). Free will is un-natural. Retrieved on 2012-08-21.
- ↑ Jump up to: 20.0 20.1 Roy F Baumeister, Matthew T Galliot, Dianne M Tice (2008). “Chapter 23: Free Willpower: A limited resource theory of volition, choice and self-regulation”, Ezequiel Morsella, John A. Bargh, Peter M. Gollwitzer: Oxford Handbook of Human Action, Volume 2 of Social Cognition and Social Neuroscience. Oxford University Press, pp. 487 ff. ISBN 0195309987.
- ↑ Sidney H Kennedy et al. (May 01, 2011). "Deep brain stimulation for treatment-resistant depression: Follow-up after 3 to 6 years". The American Journal of Psychiatry 168 (5). Retrieved on 2012-09-04.
- ↑ "Every man's world picture is and always remains a construct of the mind and cannot be proved to have any other existence, yet the conscious mind itself remains a stranger within that construct, it has no living space in it, you can spot it nowhere in space...We have entirely taken to thinking of the personality of a human being...as located in the interior of its body. To learn that it cannot really be found there is so amazing that it meets with doubt and hesitation, we are very loath to admit it." And later (p. 123) "It is very difficult for us to take stock of the fact that the localization of the personality, of the conscious mind, inside the body is only symbolic, just an aid for practical use." Reprinted in Erwin Schrödinger (2012). “Mind and Matter”, Forward by Roger Penrose: What is Life?: With Mind and Matter and Autobiographical Sketches. Cambridge University Press, p. 122. ISBN 1107604664.
- ↑ Ratner continues: "The mind-body problem of how the physical body/brain produces mental, subjective qualia, is the wrong way to frame the origin of consciousness." See: Carl Ratner (2011). Macro Cultural Psychology: A Political Philosophy of Mind. Oxford University Press, p. 96. ISBN 0199706298.
- ↑ Daniel D. Hutto, Erik Myin (2013). Radicalizing Enactivism: Basic Minds Without Content. MIT Press, p. 6. ISBN 9780262018548. “Variables in the environment influence and are influenced by variables in the brain and the non-neural body in a recurrent manner, making it impossible to conceive of these as linear relations holding between inputs and outputs...There is no way to isolate properly mentality-constituting 'inner' organismic responses from 'outer' ones that allegedly stand over and against the former as mere causal contributions from the environment.”
- ↑ Jump up to: 25.0 25.1 See for example: Sandro Nannini (2004). “Chapter 5: Mental causation and intentionality in a mind naturalizing theory”, Alberto Peruzzi, ed: Mind and Causality. John Benjamins Publishing, pp. 69 ff. ISBN 1588114759.
- ↑ John R Searle (1997). John Haugeland, ed: Mind Design II: Philosophy, Psychology, and Artificial Intelligence, 2nd ed. MIT Press, p. 203. ISBN 0262082594.
- ↑ For example, see the discussion in Steve M. Potter (2008). “What can AI get from neuroscience?”, Max Lungarella, Fumiya Iida, Josh Bongard, eds: 50 Years of Artificial Intelligence: Essays Dedicated to the 50th Anniversary of Artificial Intelligence. Springer, pp. 174 'ff. ISBN 3540772952.
- ↑ Karl Raimund Popper (1999). “Notes of a realist on the body-mind problem”, All Life is Problem Solving, A lecture given in Mannheim, 8 May, 1972. Psychology Press, pp. 23 ff. ISBN 0415174864. “The body-mind relationship...includes the problem of man's position in the physical world...'World 1'. The world of conscious human processes I shall call 'World 2', and the world of the objective creations of the human mind I shall call 'World 3'.” See also Karl Popper (April 7, 1978). Three Worlds: The Tanner Lecture on Human Values. Tanner Humanities Center, The University of Utah. Retrieved on June 1, 2015.
- ↑ Jump up to: 29.0 29.1 Ralph D Ellis (2000). “Efferent brain processes and the enactive approach to consciousness”, Nicholas Humphrey, ed: How to Solve the Mind-- Body Problem, Reprint from Journal of Consciousness Studies, 7 (4)2000, pp. 40-50. Imprint Academic, pp. 48-49. ISBN 0907845088.
- ↑ Henri Atlan (2011). “Chapter 2: Intentional self-organization: Emergence and reduction, toward a physical theory of reduction”, Todd Meyers, Stefanos Geroulanos: Henri Atlan: Selected Writings, Translation of Thesis 11 52 (February 1998): 5-34. Fordham University Press, pp. 70 ff.
- ↑ For a brief historical rundown, see James W. Kalat (2008). Biological Psychology, 10th ed. Cengage Learning, p. 7. ISBN 0495603007.
- ↑ Barry Loewer. Edward Craig, general editor: Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Volume 6. Oxford University Press, p. 310. ISBN 0415073103. referring to Nagel (What is it like to be a bat?, 1974) and to Jackson (What Mary didn't know, 1986)
- ↑ Jump up to: 33.0 33.1 33.2 Galen Strawson (2010). Freedom and belief, Revised ed. Oxford University Press, p. 6. ISBN 0199247501.
- ↑ Galen Strawson (April 19, 2011). E. Craig, ed:Free will. Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved on December 09, 2013.
- ↑ Benedict de Spinoza (2008). “Part III: On the origin and nature of the emotions; Postulates (Proposition II, Note)”, R. H. M. Elwes, trans: The Ethics, Original work published 1677. Digireads.com Publishing, p. 54. ISBN 1420931148.
- ↑ Jump up to: 36.0 36.1 Ricardo Salles (2005). The Stoics on Determinism and Compatibilism. Ashgate Publishing. ISBN 0754639762.
- ↑ Jump up to: 37.0 37.1 Keimpe Algra (1999). “Chapter VI: The Chyrsippean notion of fate: soft determinism”, The Cambridge History of Hellenistic Philosophy. Cambridge University Press, p. 529. ISBN 0521250285.
- ↑ For a discussion, see Robert C. Solomon, Kathleen M. Higgins (2009). “Free will and determinism”, The Big Questions: A Short Introduction to Philosophy, 8th. Cengage Learning, p. 232. ISBN 0495595152.
- ↑ Ernest Nagel (1999). “§V: Alternative descriptions of physical state”, The Structure of Science: Problems in the Logic of Scientific Explanation, 2nd. Hackett, 285-292. ISBN 0915144719.
- ↑ Saint Augustine, Bishop of Hippo (1993). “Introduction by translator”, On Free Choice Of The Will, Translation by Thomas Williams of Augustine's work of AD 391-395. Hackett Publishing, p. 12. ISBN 0872201880.
- ↑ Allen W Wood (1998). Patricia Kitcher, ed: Kant's Critique of Pure Reason: Critical Essays. Rowman & Littlefield, pp. 240 ff. ISBN 0847689174.
- ↑ Jump up to: 42.0 42.1 Pierre Maurice Marie Duhem (1991). The Aim and Structure of Physical Theory. Princeton University Press, p. 21. ISBN 069102524X.
- ↑ E. Bruce Goldstein (2010). Sensation and Perception, 10th ed. Cengage Learning, p. 39. ISBN 0495601497. “Solving the hard problem of consciousness involves determining how physiological processes such as ions flowing across the nerve membrane cause us to have experiences.”
- ↑ Jens Harbecke (2009). Mental Causation: Investigating the Mind's Powers in a Natural World. Ontos Verlag. ISBN 3938793945.
- ↑ Sam Harris (2012). Free Will. Simon and Schuster, p. 20. ISBN 1451683405.
- ↑ BF Skinner (2011). About Behaviorism. Random House Digital, Inc. ISBN 0307797848.
- ↑ An historical outline of the evolution of cognitive psychology and its relation to behaviorism is found in E. Bruce Goldstein (2008). “Chapter 1: Introduction to Cognitive Psychology”, Cognitive Psychology: Connecting Mind, Research, and Everyday Experience, 2nd ed. Cengage Learning, pp. 1 ff. ISBN 0495095575.
- ↑ Robert J. Sternberg (2009). “Psychological antecedents of cognitive psychology”, Cognitive Psychology, 5th ed. Cengage Learning, pp. 5 ff. ISBN 049550629X.
- ↑ This quote is from: Eric R. Kandel (2007). In Search of Memory: The Emergence of a New Science of Mind. WW Norton, p. 9. ISBN 0393329372. However, the same language can be found in dozens of sources. Some philosophers object to the unsupported statement of such conjectures, for example, observing that consciousness has yet to be shown to be a process at all, never mind a biological process. See Oswald Hanfling (2002). Wittgenstein and the Human Form of Life. Psychology Press, pp. 108-109. ISBN 0415256453.
- ↑ Jump up to: 50.0 50.1 50.2 A rather extended discussion is provided in Georg Northoff (2004). Philosophy of the Brain: The Brain Problem, Volume 52 of Advances in Consciousness Research. John Benjamins Publishing. ISBN 1588114171.
- ↑ Jump up to: 51.0 51.1 Niels Bohr (April 1, 1933). "Light and Life". Nature: p. 457 ff. Full text on line at us.archive.org.
- ↑ Gregg D Caruso (2012). Free Will and Consciousness: A Determinist Account of the Illusion of Free Will. Lexington Books. ISBN 0739171364. “One of the strongest supports for the free choice thesis is the unmistakable intuition of virtually every human being that he is free to make the choices he does and that the deliberations leading to those choices are also free flowing..”
- ↑ Ernest Nagel (1999). “§V: Alternative descriptions of physical state”, The Structure of Science: Problems in the Logic of Scientific Explanation, 2nd. Hackett, 285-292. ISBN 0915144719.
- ↑ Silvan S. Schweber (1994). QED and the men who made it: Dyson, Feynman, Schwinger, and Tomonaga. Princeton University Press. ISBN 0691033277. A more technical description is provided by Adrian Wüthrich (2010). The Genesis of Feynman Diagrams. Springer. ISBN 9048192277.
- ↑ Aaron Copland (1980). “The Charles Elliot Norton lectures, 1951-52”, Music and Imagination. Harvard University Press. ISBN 0674589157. “It [music] is at the same time outside and away from us and inside and part of us.”
- ↑ Eileen C. Shapiro (1996). “The high stakes thrill of fad surfing in the boardroom”, Fad Surfing in the Boardroom: Managing in the Age of Instant Answers. Basic Books. ISBN 0201441950.
- ↑ David Swartz (1998). “The subjective/objective antimony”, Culture and Power: The Sociology of Pierre Bourdieu, 2nd. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 0226785955.
- ↑ Alec Rogers (2012). “The division between subjective and objective defines life”, Cognitive Set Theory. ArborRhythms. ISBN 0983037604.
- ↑ Andrew Whitaker (2006). Einstein, Bohr And the Quantum Dilemma: From Quantum Theory to Quantum Information, 2nd ed. Cambridge University Press, p. 191. ISBN 0521671027.
- ↑ For a discussion of a program to establish complementarity as speculated by Bohr, see Paul McEvoy (2001). Niels Bohr: Reflections on Subject and Object. MicroAnalytix, p. 323. ISBN 1930832001.
- ↑ Jump up to: 61.0 61.1 Susan Pockett (2009). “The neuroscience of movement”, Susan Pockett, WP Banks, Shaun Gallagher, eds: Does Consciousness Cause Behavior?. MIT Press, p. 19. ISBN 0262512572.
- ↑ Neils Bohr. The Atomic Theory and the Fundamental Principles underlying the Description of Nature; Based on a lecture to the Scandinavian Meeting of Natural Scientists and published in Danish in Fysisk Tidsskrift in 1929. First published in English in 1934 by Cambridge University Press.. The Information Philosopher, dedicated to the new information philosophy. Robert O. Doyle, publisher. Retrieved on 2012-09-14.
- ↑ Nader El-Bizri (2000). The Phenomenological Quest Between Avicenna and Heidegger. Global Academic Publishing, pp. 97-98. ISBN 1586840053.
- ↑
As translated with artistic license by Eric Scigliano:
- "The finest artist can't conceive a thought
- that the marble itself does not bind
- within its shell, waiting to be brought
- out by the hand that serves the artist's mind."
- ↑ Georg Northoff (2004). Philosophy of the Brain: The Brain Problem, Volume 52 of Advances in Consciousness Research. John Benjamins Publishing, pp. 137-139. ISBN 1588114171.
- ↑ Jump up to: 66.0 66.1 66.2 Walter J Freeman (2009). “Consciousness, intentionality and causality”, Susan Pockett, WP Banks, Shaun Gallagher, eds: Does Consciousness Cause Behavior?. MIT Press, p. 88. ISBN 0262512572.
- ↑ J. A. Scott Kelso (1995). Dynamic Patterns: The Self-Organization of Brain and Behavior. MIT Press, p. 16. ISBN 0262611317. “An order parameter is created by the correlation between the parts, but in turn influences the behavior of the parts. This is what we mean by circular causality.” Kelso also says (p. 9): "But add a few more parts interlaced together and very quickly it becomes impossible to treat the system in terms of feedback circuits. In such complex systems, ... the concept of feedback is inadequate.[...] there is no reference state with which feedback can be compared and no place where comparison operations are performed."
- ↑ Namhee Lee, Lisa Mikesell, Anna Dina L. Joaquin, Andrea W. Mates, John H. Schumann (2009). “Feedback and circular causality”, The Interactional Instinct: The Evolution and Acquisition of Language. Oxford University Press, pp. 26 ff. ISBN 0195384237.
- ↑ Hermann Haken (2006). Information and Self-Organization: A Macroscopic Approach to Complex Systems, 3rd ed. Springer, p. 25. ISBN 3540330216.
- ↑ Drew McDermott (2007). “Chapter 6: Artificial intelligence and consciousness”, Philip David Zelazo, Morris Moscovitch, Evan Thompson, eds: The Cambridge Handbook of Consciousness. Cambridge University Press, pp. 117 ff. ISBN 0521857430.
- ↑ Rebecca Stefoff (2007). Robots. Marshall Cavendish, p. 118. ISBN 0761426019.
- ↑ Kerstin Dautenhahn (2000). Human Cognition and Social Agent Technology. John Benjamins Publishing Company, p. 202. ISBN 9027251398.
- ↑ Jump up to: 73.0 73.1 This field is sometimes called Darwinian engineering or evolutionary robotics. See for example, Stéphane Doncieux, Jean-Baptiste Mouret, Nicolas Bredechte, Vincent Padois (2011). “Chapter 1: Evolutionary robotics: exploring new horizons”, Stéphane Doncieux, ed: New Horizons in Evolutionary Robotics: Extended Contributions from the 2009 EvoDeRob Workshop. Springer, pp. 3 ff. ISBN 3642182712.
- ↑ Barbara Creed (2009). “Intelligent machines and created life forms”, Darwin's Screens: Evolutionary Aesthetics, Time and Sexual Display in the Cinema. Academic Monographs, pp. 65 ff. ISBN 0522857094.
- ↑ J. Kozielecki (1981). “§1.3 The structure of psychological decision theory”, Psychological Decision Theory. Springer Science & Business Media, p. 11. ISBN 9789027710512.
- ↑ Nick Chater (2012). “Chapter 4: Building blocks of human decision making”, Peter Hammerstein, Jeffrey R. Stevens, eds: Evolution and the Mechanisms of Decision Making. MIT Press, 53-68. ISBN 9780262018081.
- ↑ Catriona Mackenzie (2014). “Chapter 21: Autonomy”, John D. Arras, Elizabeth Fenton, Rebecca Kukla, eds: The Routledge Companion to Bioethics. Routledge, pp. 277 ff. ISBN 9781136644849.
- ↑ How can I tell if I have a drinking problem? One determinant is: "If you sometimes get drunk when you fully intend to stay sober." (2006) “Alcoholism: Questions and answers”, Johannes P. Schade, ed: The Complete Encyclopedia of Medicine & Health. Foreign Media Group, p. 134. ISBN 1601360010.
- ↑ One mechanism of addiction is the interruption of recycling of dopamine into a transmitting neuron by blocking of dopamine transporters, resulting in a build-up of dopamine in the synapse. See, for example, Katherine Van Wormer, Diane Rae Davis (2012). “Caption to Figure 3.4”, Addiction Treatment, 3rd ed. Cengage Learning, p. 154. ISBN 0840029160. For a discussion of therapy, see for example Carol Mattson Porth (2008). “Disorders of Abuse and Addiction”, Pathophysiology: Concepts of Altered Health States, 8th ed. Lippincott Williams & Wilkins, p. 1316 ff. ISBN 1605473901. Link is to the Canadian edition.
- ↑ Jump up to: 80.0 80.1 Nora D Volkow, Joanna S Fowler, and Gene-Jack Wang (2007). “The addicted human brain: insights from imaging studies”, Andrew R Marks and Ushma S Neill, eds: Science In Medicine: The JCI Textbook Of Molecular Medicine. Jones & Bartlett Learning, pp. 1061 ff. ISBN 0763750832.
- ↑ Benjamin Libet et al. (1983). "Time of conscious intention to act in relation to onset of cerebral activity (readiness-potential).". Brain 106: 623-642.
- ↑ Lars Strother, Sukhvinder Singh Obhi (2009). "The conscious experience of action and intention". Exp Brain Res 198: 535-539. DOI:10.1007/s00221-009-1946-7. Research Blogging.
- ↑ A brief discussion of possible interpretation of these results is found in David A. Rosenbaum (2009). Human Motor Control, 2nd ed. Academic Press, p. 86. ISBN 0123742269.
- ↑ Shaun Gallagher (2009). “Chapter 6: Where's the action? Epiphenomenalism and the problem of free will”, Susan Pockett, William P. Banks, Shaun Gallagher, eds: Does Consciousness Cause Behavior?. MIT Press, pp. 119-121. ISBN 0262512572.
- ↑ Jump up to: 85.0 85.1 John Tooby, Leda Cosmides (2006). “Conceptual foundations of evolutionary psychology”, David M Buss, ed: The Handbook of Evolutionary Psychology. John Wiley & Sons, pp. 53-54. ISBN 0471264032.
- ↑ Note: A humunculus is a little person inside the head that carries out mental functions.
- ↑ Willis F Overton (2003). “Chapter 1: Development across the life span”, Lerner, M. Ann Easterbrooks, Jayanthi Mistry: Handbook of Psychology, Developmental Psychology, Volume 6 of Handbook of Psychology. John Wiley & Sons, pp. 13 ff. ISBN 0471264474.
- ↑ Irwin Silverman, Jean Choi (2006). “Locating places”, David M Buss, ed: The Handbook of Evolutionary Psychology. John Wiley & Sons, p. 180. ISBN 0471264032.
- ↑ Epigenetics. Nova Beta. Produced for PBS Online by WGBH Educational Foundation.
- ↑ Yongsheng Liu (September 2007). Like father like son. A fresh review of the inheritance of acquired characteristics. EMBO Reports. The European Molecular Biology Organization EMBO Rep. 2007 September; 8(9): 798-803. PMC1973965 DOI=10.1038/sj.embor.7401060
- ↑ Root Gorelick (2004). "Neo-Lamarckian medicine". Medical Hypotheses 62: pp. 299-303. DOI:10.1016/S0306-9877(03)00329-3. Research Blogging.
- ↑ Keith E. Stanovich (2005). The Robot's Rebellion: Finding Meaning in the Age of Darwin. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 0226771253. See in particular Chapter 8: A soul without mystery, pp. 207 ff.
- ↑ Daniel M. Wegner (2003). The Illusion of Conscious Will. MIT Press. ISBN 0262731622.
- ↑ Lewis Mumford (1974). “Chapter 3 §2: The Crime of Galileo”, The Myth of the Machine - Book 2: The Pentagon of Power. Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, p. 57. ISBN 9780156716109. “Galileo committed a crime far graver than any the dignitaries of the Church accused him of; for his real crime was that of trading the totality of human experience...for that minute portion which can observed within a limited time-span and interpreted in terms of mass and motion, while denying importance to the unmediated realities of human experience, from which science itself is only a refined ideological derivative.”
- ↑ Thomas S. Kuhn (1996). The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. University of Chicago Press, p. 51. ISBN 9780226458083. “Still,...that paradigm change cannot be justified by proof, is not to say that no arguments are relevant, or that scientists cannot be persuaded to change their minds...Furthermore, these conversions occur not despite the fact that scientists are human but because they are.”